Return
to Animals Issue contents
5.
CONTRACTUALISM AND ANIMALS
In this chapter I shall consider what a
contractualist should say about the moral standing of animals. Throughout, I
shall make the simplifying assumption that no animals should be counted as
rational agents, in the sense that is central to contractualism. The extent to
which this assumption is true will be examined in the chapter that follows.
Rawlss
contractualism and animals
According to Rawls, we are to think of
morality as the set of rules that would be agreed upon by rational agents
choosing from behind a veil of ignorance. While these agents are supposed to
have knowledge of all general truths of psychology, economics, and so on, they
are to be ignorant of their own particular qualities (their intelligence,
physical strength, projects, and desires), as well as the position they will
occupy in the resulting society. Their choice of moral principles is to be made
in the light of broadly self-interested desires (such as those for happiness,
freedom, and power), that the agents know they will possess whatever particular
desires and interests they subsequently come to have.
Morality
is here pictured as a system of rules to govern the interaction of rational
agents within society. It therefore seems inevitable, on the face of it, that
only rational agents will be assigned direct rights on this approach. Since it
is rational agents who are to choose the system of rules, and choose
self-interestedly, it is only rational agents who will have their position
protected under the rules. There seems no reason why rights should be assigned
to non-rational agents. Animals will therefore have no moral standing under
Rawlsian contractualism, in so far as they do not count as rational agents.
It
might be suggested that there is, after all, a way in which rights can come to
be assigned to animals under contractualism. This is by some of the agents
behind the veil of ignorance being detailed to speak on behalf of non-rational
agents, their task being to represent the interests of animals in the
formulation of the basic contract. Compare the way in which a lawyer may
represent the interests of a pet dog in a court of law, in a dispute over the
deceased owners will. The idea is that behind the veil of ignorance, as in the
law court, someone may be detailed to speak for those who are incapable of
speaking for themselves.
Notice,
however, that even if this extension of Rawlss theory were acceptable, it
would still not yield anything like the common-sense view of animals. On the
contrary, it would lead to animals being accorded equal rights with human beings, consistent with their different
needs and capacities. (Thus one would not expect that animals could have an
equal right to own property, since they are incapable of buying and selling.
But they could have an equal right to life, and an equal right not to be made
to suffer.) There is no reason why the animal representatives behind the veil
of ignorance should settle for anything less. For remember that the people in
this position are not supposed to have, as yet, any moral beliefs. So the
representatives of animal interests cannot accept as a reason for according
animals unequal status, that animals have lower moral importance than human
beings. But the idea that animals should be given equal standing with ourselves
is a good deal more extreme than we should be prepared to accept, as we have
seen over the last two chapters.
Another
problem with the above suggestion is this. Once it is allowed that animals may
have representatives to speak on their behalf behind the veil of ignorance,
there seems no good theoretical reason why other sorts of thing should not have
representatives also. Why should there not be people detailed to defend plants
and micro-organisms, or indeed mountains and ancient buildings? Moral rights
would then become rampant, in a way that would, I think, be acceptable to no
one.
The
main objection to allowing representatives of animal interests behind the veil
of ignorance, however, is that it is arbitrary. It has been done without any
independent theoretical rationale, simply to secure the desired result - that
animals should have moral standing. Now it might seem that this charge is
unfair. For as Rawls stresses, the business of theory-construction in morality
is, at least partly, a matter of seeking reflective equilibrium. Although moral
beliefs should not be directly mentioned within our theory, it is a constraint
on a theory being acceptable that it should deliver a good many, at least, of
our firmly held moral convictions. And we do have moral convictions about the
appropriate treatment of animals. So it might be said that allowing
representatives to speak on behalf of animals behind the veil of ignorance is
just the sort of theoretical alteration that we ought to have expected to make
all along.
While
I have endorsed the method of reflective equilibrium in ethics, I do not think
that it can be successful in defending the current proposal. One reason for
this is that the proposal does not, in any case, deliver the common-sense view
of animals, as I pointed out above. But a more important reason is as follows.
As initially presented, the idea of choice of moral principles from a position
of ignorance constituted a coherent vision of the nature and source of
morality. Moral rules were seen as those that rational agents would agree on to
govern their conduct with respect to one another, if they employed only general
rational considerations in their choice, not allowing themselves to be
influenced by facts about their own particular interests or position within
society. But if some of these agents are detailed to represent the interests of
animals in the selection of moral rules, this coherence vanishes. It is then no
longer clear what morality is.
Indeed, it appears that we would have to say - circularly - that morality is
the set of rules that would be agreed upon by rational agents who already had a
prior belief in the moral standing of animals.
Regans
reply
Regan has mounted an argument designed to
show that contractualism cannot coherently withhold moral standing from
animals, without also withholding it from those human beings who are not
rational agents, such as severe mental defectives or senile old people.[1]
I shall defer considering the latter part of this charge until later sections,
where it will turn out that Regan seriously underestimates the resources
available to contractualists, through which they can explain how all human
beings should be accorded the same basic moral rights, whatever their mental
capacities. Here I shall consider Regans argument that Rawlsian contractualism
is theoretically arbitrary to the extent that it denies moral standing to
animals.
Regan
claims that if agents behind the veil of ignorance are to be ignorant of such
fundamental matters as their qualities of character, life-plans, and position
within society, then there is no good reason why they should not also be
ignorant of their species. But if the agents were to be ignorant of the species
into which they would subsequently be incarnated, when selecting basic moral
principles, then, plainly, they would choose rules protecting the interests of
members of all species equally. So Rawls has simply begged the question against
the moral standing of animals in the manner in which he sets up the apparatus
of the veil of ignorance. Had he arranged the details of that device slightly
differently, then animals would have been accorded the same basic rights as
human beings within contractualism.
Now,
I do not wish to suggest that there is anything sacrosanct about the way in
which Rawls characterises the details of the veil of ignorance. (On the
contrary, it is plain that a simple extension of his ideas would deliver a
strong environmental ethic, that would at the same time be theoretically
motivated. We need only suppose that the agents behind the veil of ignorance
should have a desire to inhabit a healthy environment, besides desires for the
primary goods of happiness, freedom, and power. This would immediately lead to
agreement on principles that protect the environment. Yet it would have a
theoretical rationale, in that rational agents may surely know that, whatever
else they may want, they will also wish to live in an environment that is
healthy and pleasant.) Nevertheless, I do not think that the extension
suggested by Regan - that agents behind the veil of ignorance should be
ignorant of their species - is a coherent one, as I shall now try to explain.
An
initial problem is that Regan misinterprets Rawls. He takes him to believe that
the veil of ignorance is a genuine metaphysical possibility - that rational
agents might really exist in ignorance of their character, desires, strength,
sex, and social position, perhaps as disembodied souls - whereas it is, for
Rawls, only a device for bracketing unwanted knowledge, whose point is to
ensure that we should not, in the construction of moral principles, appeal to
knowledge that might undermine the reasonableness of the result.[2]
This does not yet dispose of Regans argument, however. For it is presumably
possible that rational agents should bracket their status as rational agents,
even in the very process of rationally constructing a system of rules. If they
can forbear from making use of their knowledge of their sex or social status,
then presumably they can just as well forbear from making use of their
knowledge of their species or, indeed, of the fact that they are rational
agents.
The
real line of reply to Regan is that his suggestion would destroy the
theoretical coherence of Rawlsian contractualism. As Rawls has it, morality is,
in fact, a human construction (in the absence, that is, of any other known
species of rational agent - a point I shall return to in the next chapter).
Morality is viewed as constructed by
human beings, in order to facilitate interactions between human beings, and to make possible a life of co-operative
community. This is, indeed, an essential part of the governing conception of
contractualism. It is crucial to its explanation of how moral notions can
arise, avoiding the excesses of intuitionism and strong objectivism. It is also
presupposed by contractualist accounts of the source of moral motivation,
whether in the Rawlsian version (to make peaceful human community possible in
conditions of modernity) or in my own, where the basic contractualist concept
(as well as the desire to comply with it) is held to be innate, selected for in
evolution because of its value in promoting the survival of our species. To
suggest, now, that contractualism should be so construed as to accord equal
moral standing to animals would be to lose our grip on where moral notions are
supposed to come from, or why we should care about them when they arrive.
It
may be objected that this line of reply to Regan implausibly reduces morality
to anthropology. But in fact it does no such thing. My claim is not that moral
statements are really disguised claims about the conditions for the survival of
the species. On the contrary, they are about what rational agents should
reasonably accept who share the aim of reaching free and unforced agreement. My
claim is only that we have this concept of morality innately, and have an
innate desire to justify our actions in terms that others may freely accept,
because doing so has promoted the survival of our species in the past. But if
the contractualist concept expresses what morality is, for us, then there is no moral stand-point from which it can be
criticised, or from which it can be argued that we are morally required to
extend that concept so as to accord equal moral standing to animals.
I
conclude, therefore, that Regan is mistaken. Rawls is by no means arbitrary in
allowing agents behind the veil of ignorance to have knowledge of their species
and their status as rational agents. On the contrary, this is crucial to ensure
the plausibility of the contractualist governing conception of the source of
moral notions and moral motivation.
Scanlons
contractualism and animals
The points made above in reply to Regan
strongly suggest that the exclusion of moral standing from animals is entailed
by contractualism as such, rather than by any mere quirk of Rawlss
presentation. As a cross-check on this, let us briefly consider how animals
would fare under Scanlons version of contractualism, in which the agents
concerned are supposed to be real ones, possessing full knowledge of their own
idiosyncratic desires and qualities, and their position within the current
structure of society. Recall that on Scanlons account, moral rules are those
that no one could reasonably reject as a basis for free, unforced, agreement,
who shares the aim of reaching such agreement. The only idealisations made are
that choices and objections will always be rational, and that all concerned
will share the aim of reaching such an agreement.
We
still have here a coherent vision of the nature of morality - indeed,
essentially the same vision as is presented in Rawlss contractualism. Since
Scanlons model deals with real agents, however, with their individual desires
and concerns, and since many real agents care deeply about the welfare of some
or all animals, there is then a genuine question as to whether such people
might not reasonably reject rules that give no weight to the interests of
animals. It may be that animals will turn out to have moral standing in this
version of contractualism, because many of the contracting parties care deeply
about them.
What
we need to know is, what counts as a reasonable basis on which to reject a
proposed rule? It seems clear at least that it will not be reasonable for
someone to reject a rule, if others would have an equal basis on which to
reject any proposed rule. For in that
case we should not be able to satisfy our shared aim of reaching free and
unforced general agreement. It cannot be reasonable, therefore, to reject a rule
merely because it conflicts with some interest or concern of mine. For every
rule (except the entirely trivial) will conflict with someones concerns.
Perhaps I care deeply about the welfare of animals. But then others care deeply
about standards of dress and appearance, modes of sexual activity, and the
worship of their God. If I can reasonably reject rules that accord no weight to
the interests of animals, then others can equally reasonably reject rules that
allow us to dress and make love as we wish, and to worship or not worship as we
please. Even rules against killing might be equally reasonably rejected by some
people, since they may want very much to kill those who stand in their way.
What
can be reasonably rejected, are rules
that accord no weight to my interests in general, or rules that allow my
privacy to be invaded, or my projects to be interfered with, at the whim of
other people. For since I know that others will similarly have reason to reject
a rule that allows me to interfere in their lives, yet since I desire that we
should agree on some rules to govern our conduct, I shall be happy to give up
my right to interfere in the lives of others in order to gain an equal
protection against interference in my own life. Indeed, it appears that here,
as before, the basic principle that we should agree upon is one of respect for
the autonomy of rational agents.
I
therefore conclude that Scanlons contractualism, like Rawlss, will fail to
give moral standing to animals, in so far as animals do not themselves have the
status of rational agents. But let me stress again that this is not to say that
a contractualist cannot care very deeply about animals. The point is that not
all cares and concerns are moral ones. Just as someone can care deeply about architecture
without believing that some buildings have moral standing, or that those
buildings have a right to be preserved (not derivative from the fact that
people such as themselves care deeply about them); in the same way one can be
an animal lover without thinking that animals have rights.
Two
varieties of indirect significance
The claim that animals must lack moral
standing under contractualism does not necessarily imply that one can, with
impunity, do whatever one wishes with respect to any animal. For they may yet
have indirect moral significance. This remains to be investigated. The issue is
important because we do need to consider whether contractualism can at least
approach our common-sense attitude to animals. If contractualism cannot explain
any of our ordinary moral judgements in this domain, then that will count
against its acceptability as a moral theory, under reflective equilibrium. Two
obvious ways in which contractualism might accord indirect moral significance
to animals, would be to subsume animals under the rules dealing with private
property, or by treating them as a matter of legitimate public interest. Let us
consider each of these in turn.
If
contractualism would condone a system of property rights, as seems plausible,
then it is clear that at least some animals will be protected by those rights.
If you have the right against me that I should not, other things being equal,
destroy your property, then I am morally obliged not to kill your dog, just as
I am obliged not to set light to your car. But notice that it is your rights that I would infringe, not
the dogs. Indeed, the dog would have no rights, any more than the car does.
Notice, moreover, that a great many animals, including those in the wild, will
not be protected by property rights, since they have no owners (though some may
receive legal protection in national parks or game reserves). More importantly,
perhaps, even those animals that have owners will receive no protection against
their owners. Since I am within my rights to batter or destroy my car, if I
choose to do so, I should also be within my rights to batter or destroy my dog,
on this approach. It seems that an appeal to property rights cannot take us
very far in attempting to reconcile contractualism with common-sense attitudes.
A
more plausible approach would be to appeal to the fact that many people care
deeply about animals. For this may then make the manner of our treatment of
animals a matter of legitimate public interest. Compare the fact that many
people care deeply about architecture and the aesthetics of their environment.
This may be sufficient to give rise to a moral duty, on the part of the owners
of some attractive ancient building, not to destroy or alter it, except for
very powerful reasons (such as that the building has, through previous neglect,
become a danger to life). The general point is that one might expect
contracting rational agents to reject rules that place no side-constraints on
the rights of ownership. Where the objects privately owned are nevertheless a
matter of legitimate public enjoyment or interest, it may be reasonable that
owners rights of disposal of their property should be constrained, to some
degree.
Similarly,
then, in the case of animals. Since many people have concerns for animals, and
are deeply distressed at seeing an animal suffer, this may place on us an
obligation not to cause suffering to animals, except for powerful reasons. This
would not be because needlessly causing such suffering would violate the rights
of the animal, any more than someone who defaces a beautiful building violates
the rights of the building. On this approach animals, like buildings, would
have no direct rights or moral standing. Rather, causing suffering to an animal
would violate the right of animal lovers to have their concerns respected and
taken seriously.
Such
an approach may be able to recover for contractualism a great deal of what
common-sense tells us about the moral treatment of animals. In particular, it
can explain how it can be true that, while we do have duties towards animals,
their lives and interests cannot be weighed against the lives and interests of
humans. For the duties in question only arise indirectly, out of respect for
those who care about animals. And this duty of respect may surely be overridden
where someones more fundamental interests or very life are threatened. Thus
consider, once again, the example of the ancient building. If the building is
the owners only residence, and if structural changes are necessary to make it
habitable, then it is surely permissible that it should be altered, overriding
the interests of the wider public.
Just
how strong would the side-constraints on animal suffering be, on this approach,
resulting from the legitimate feelings of animal lovers? Plainly, as we have
just seen, they would fail to rule out actions causing suffering to animals
that are necessary to subserve some important human concern, such as, arguably,
the testing of new medicines upon animals. But more importantly, the constraints
would only apply to suffering that occurs in a manner that is unavoidably
public. So, in particular, painful methods of factory farming, and the testing
of detergents on animals, would not be ruled out, even granting that the
purposes subserved by such activities (cheaper meat, and new varieties of
shampoo) are trivial. For it seems that one can legitimately reply to those who
complain of such activities in exactly the way that one would reply to those
who are distressed by unusual sexual practices, for example. One can say, If
it upsets you, dont think about it. While granting that an unusual sexual
practice (or the suffering of an animal) should not be flaunted in public,
because of the offence this may occasion, it seems there can be no objection to
it occurring in private. So while the present suggestion concerning the
contractualist attitude to animals can accommodate a good deal of common-sense
belief, it gives no support to those who are currently campaigning on behalf of
factory farmed and laboratory animals.
The
present approach does face difficulties, however, quite apart from its
consequences for the controversial practices of factory farming and laboratory
testing. For there are two important elements of common-sense moral belief that
it cannot accommodate. The first is that duties towards animals can arise
equally in the private as in the public domain. While the approach can explain
why it may be wrong to severely beat a dog in the street, it is not obvious why
it should also be wrong to torture a cat in the privacy of your own home. For
those people who would be distressed by the cats suffering, were they to
observe it, will in fact remain unaware of it. Yet it may be said that such an
action would still, intuitively, be very wrong. Secondly, it is also part of
common-sense belief that cruelty to an animal is wrong because of what is done
to the animal, not because of any suffering caused to sympathetic human
observers, as the present approach would suggest.
There
is perhaps more that contractualists can say in their defence along these
general lines. For example, since animals, unlike most items of property, are
capable of independent motion, there is a greater risk that supposedly private
actions may become public. If the cat were to manage to escape from me into the
public domain while I am torturing her, then other people may yet become
distressed at her condition. Such considerations are plainly pretty weak,
however, as the following development of the example of Astrid, the astronaut, will
make especially clear.
Recall
that Astrid has left Earth on a space-rocket, on an irreversible trajectory
that will take her out of the solar system and forever out of contact with her
fellow human beings. Now in her rocket she carries with her a cat, and a famous
work of art of which she is the legitimate owner (the Mona Lisa, say). As the years pass she becomes bored with her books
and tapes, and seeks alternative entertainment. Then contrast two cases: in the
first case she removes the glass cover from the Mona Lisa and uses the painting as a dart-board; in the second case
she ties the cat to the wall and uses it
as a dart-board. I think we should feel intuitively that there is a very great
difference, morally speaking, between these two cases. This cannot be explained
on the hypothesis that our duties towards animals, as towards beautiful
objects, arise only out of the likely effect of our actions on the feelings of
other people. For both cases are alike in that it can be known that there will
be no such effect.
I
think I would be prepared to grant that Astrid does nothing wrong in throwing
darts at the Mona Lisa. I may regret
her philistinism, but cannot claim that she violates any rights or omits any
moral duties. For it is in any case true that no one else is ever going to see
the painting again. (I might say that Astrid had acted wrongly in taking such a
great painting with her in the first place, but that is another matter.) In
contrast, it is surely wrong of Astrid to throw darts at the cat out of idle
amusement, despite the fact that she may be quite certain that no person will
ever become distressed at what she has done, since no one will ever know. I
therefore conclude that contractualism cannot accommodate all of what
common-sense tells us about the moral treatment of animals, by trying to give
animals an indirect moral significance based upon the fact that many people
care deeply about them. We face a choice, at this point, of either giving up
contractualist approaches to morality, or giving up some common-sense beliefs.
It
might be argued that the conflict with ordinary belief on this matter is not a
serious problem for contractualism, since it only really arises in connection
with imaginary examples. For in any real case of private cruelty to an animal
there will be a danger that the public should become aware of it. But there are
two replies to this. The first is that imaginary examples cannot be belittled
merely because they are imaginary. When we consider the case of Astrid, the
astronaut, we feel very strongly that it would be wrong of her to throw darts
at her cat. This attitude has as much right as any other to be considered as
part of common-sense, even though the example is not real. For the way in which
we respond to that example is perfectly real. The second reply is that
common-sense does not, in any case, merely tell us that cruelty to an animal is
wrong. It also tells us that it is wrong because of what is done to the animal,
rather than because of the effects on a likely observer. This has not yet been
accounted for.
A
problem for reflective equilibrium
As we have just seen, there is a problem for
contractualism in attempting to reconcile itself with our common-sense beliefs
concerning the appropriate moral treatment of animals. I propose to leave this
aside for the moment. I shall return to it in Chapter 7, where I shall show how
contractualism can achieve reflective equilibrium on these matters. I shall now
pursue a more direct and serious challenge. For contractualism does not just
come into apparent conflict with common-sense morality in connection with
animals. It also faces difficulties concerning the moral treatment of those
human beings who are not, on any account of the matter, rational agents, such
as young babies, very senile old people, or severe mental defectives. This is a
much more serious difficulty, since the beliefs in question are more centrally
embedded within common-sense morality.
If
animals are not accorded moral standing under contractualism, on the grounds
that they are not rational agents, then it would seem that by the same token
all those human beings who are not rational agents will also fail to have moral
standing bestowed on them. In which case killing a baby or a senile human being
would not violate their rights, since they would have no rights. Such killings
would at most violate our duty to respect the feelings of those people who care
about babies (or that particular baby) or the senile. This is, to say the
least, counter-intuitive.
In
the case of babies there may be more that a contractualist can say to explain
the wrongness of causing them suffering. For such suffering may be expected to
have an effect on the rational agents they will one day become. Our actions may
thus directly violate the rights of those future persons, and hence be wrong
even when done in private so as to cause no distress to others. In the same
way, contractualists may be able to explain the wrongness of killing babies, if
they are prepared to accept the principle that it is wrong to prevent a
rational agent from coming into existence. (What they say about this will
clearly have implications for their attitude towards abortion and
contraception.) But they cannot similarly explain the wrongness of killing or
causing suffering to mental defectives or senile old people, since such human
beings no longer have the potential, in general, to become rational agents.
To
make the case as strong as possible, consider again the example of Astrid, the
astronaut. Suppose that Astrid has taken her grandfather with her, who becomes
increasingly senile as the journey progresses. Would it not be very wrong of
her to start using him as a
dart-board to relieve her tedium, or to kill him because the sight of his
dribbling offends her? Yet on what grounds can such actions be wrong, if only
rational agents have moral standing? For no other person will ever be worried
or upset at the suffering or death of her grandfather.
It
appears that contractualism faces severe difficulties in accommodating our
common-sense attitudes towards those living beings who are not rational agents.
Since these attitudes are even more deeply entrenched in connection with
non-rational human beings than they are in connection with animals, any attempt
to brush common-sense beliefs aside, on the grounds of their conflict with the
theory of contractualism, will be correspondingly weaker. For example, no one
is going to accept the testing of detergents on the senile, or the hunting of
mental defectives for sport. If we cannot find some other way of handling these
examples within contractualism, it would appear that the latter is doomed as an
acceptable moral theory. I shall now consider a number of different ways in
which contractualists might respond.
Family
lines and the prospect of senility
Rawls himself has a way of securing direct
moral rights for all human beings. This is by making the agents behind the veil
of ignorance choose on behalf, not just of themselves, but of family lines.[3]
The main point of this proposal for Rawls, is to give the same weight to future
generations as to the people of the present in the application of the
difference principle - arguing, for example, that it would be wrong of us to
exhaust the Earths natural resources. But the proposal is equally serviceable
in according rights to babies, the senile, and mental defectives. For it has
the effect of securing the same moral rights, not just for all rational agents,
but also for all children of rational agents. Then since every human being -
whether baby, senile, or mental defective - is the child of (or, at any rate,
is descended from) rational agents, the conclusion will be that all human
beings have the same basic moral rights. But since no animals are descended
from rational agents, we are supposing, no animals will have direct rights.
The
first thing that needs to be asked, is whether the position can be properly
theoretically motivated. Or is it theoretically arbitrary, like the suggestion
discussed earlier, that some people behind the veil of ignorance might be
delegated to represent the interests of animals? Remember that those behind the
veil of ignorance are to have knowledge of all general facts about the human
condition, as well as about human psychology. They will therefore know that it
is highly likely that they will have children, and that they will care very
deeply what happens to those children. It then appears entirely reasonable that
they should insist on direct rights for all children of rational agents (and
hence for all human beings). Rather than being arbitrary, the present proposal
flows directly from Rawlss characterisation of the veil of ignorance.
This
is one of those places where the artificiality of Rawlss construction may
matter, however. For it is not nearly so obvious that the above argument can
survive translation into other varieties of contractualism. Consider Scanlons
version, for example. Many real agents know that they will never have children.
Others may know that their parents have died before becoming senile. Such persons
might, it seems, reasonably reject rules according direct moral rights to
babies, mental defectives, or the senile. This is in just the same way that
those who know that they are indifferent to art may reasonably reject the
proposal put forward by the majority of people who are art-lovers, that works
of art should be accorded direct moral rights. If we are to find convincing
contractualist arguments for according moral standing to all human beings, it
seems we should look elsewhere.
A
different suggestion is as follows. As a rational agent I know that it is
likely that I shall, one day, slide gradually into a condition of senility. I
also know that it is possible for an accident to reduce me to the level of a
severe mental defective, or a baby. But, it is claimed, I would surely wish to
preserve for myself the same basic moral rights and protections in those
circumstances as I now enjoy. If I were actually in a state of senility, of
course, I should be in no position rationally to reject a system of rules
withholding moral rights from the senile. But I may now rationally reject such
rules, on the grounds that they conflict with what I want for myself were I to
become senile, and since I can see that all have as much reason as myself to
reject such rules.
If
the argument above were successful, then we might be able to move on to grant
moral standing to all human beings, irrespective of their cognitive powers.
For, given that moral standing is to be accorded to those who become senile, or severely subnormal as
a result of an accident, it would surely be intolerable that moral standing
should be withheld from those who are born
so. And then if moral standing is granted to those who, as adults, are
congenitally severely subnormal, it would seem that there can be no rational
basis for withholding it from young babies, who may enjoy similar levels of
cognitive activity.
There
are two reasons why this attempt to extend the same basic rights to all human
beings must fail, however. The first is relatively simple. It is that not
everyone wishes that they should continue to enjoy the same moral protections
were they to become senile. It is common for people to say, indeed, (especially
as the prospect of senility becomes increasingly real) that they only hope that
someone has the nerve to kill them off quickly once they reach that state. The
second reason for failure is more deeply metaphysical. It is, that it is
doubtful whether personal identity can be preserved through cognitive changes
as massive as the slide into senility. Although at the end of such a change the
very same human being (or physical body) would still exist, of course, it is
highly doubtful whether I would any
longer exist. For the resulting human being would have none of the same
beliefs, desires, interests, memories, or qualities of character that -
arguably - constitute my identity as a person.[4]
This, too, accords with ordinary parlance. It is common for people to say of
their friends or relatives in such circumstances, such things as It is not
really Granny in that hospital ward, any longer. But if, following the slide
into senility, the resulting person is not me, then I cannot now self-interestedly reject rules that
affect that person. Yet this is what I would have to be able to do, if the
senile are to be accorded moral standing, on this approach.
Slippery
slopes and social stability
There is a very different way in which
contractualists, of whatever variety, can attempt to secure direct moral rights
for all human beings. As with the Rawlss suggestion, this one, too, will leave
animals without moral standing. The strategy depends upon the fact that there
are no sharp boundaries between a baby and an adult, between a
not-very-intelligent adult and a severe mental defective, or between a normal
old person and someone who is severely senile. The argument is then that the
attempt to accord direct moral rights only to rational agents (normal adults)
would be inherently dangerous and open to abuse.
This
is, of course, a version of slippery slope argument. The suggestion is that if
we try to deny moral rights to some human beings, on the grounds that they are
not rational agents, we shall be launched on a slippery slope which may lead to
all kinds of barbarisms against those who are
rational agents. It is important to be clear about the level on which this
argument is supposed to operate, however. For there is nothing to stop us, at
the level of theory, from insisting that only rational agents have rights,
leaving a large range of cases in which possession of rights would be
indeterminate. Or we could insist that possession of rights itself should be a
matter of degree, the killing of a human being becoming more and more serious,
in terms of direct infringements of right, as a baby gradually advances into
adulthood. There would be nothing incoherent in these theories as such. The
claim must be that it is in the application of these theories in the real world
that the danger lies. The idea is that such theories would be inherently
susceptible to abuse by unscrupulous people, and ought therefore not to be
adopted.
In
contrast, there really is a sharp boundary between human beings and all other
animals. Not necessarily in terms of intelligence or degree of rational agency,
of course - a chimpanzee may be more intelligent than a mentally defective
human, and a dolphin may be a rational agent to a higher degree than a human
baby. But there is not the same practical threat to the welfare of rational
agents in the suggestion that all animals should be excluded from the domain of
direct moral concern. Someone who argues that since animals do not have rights,
therefore babies do not have rights, therefore there can be no moral objection
to the extermination of Jews, Gypsies, Gays and other so-called deviants, is
unlikely to be taken very seriously, even by those who share their evil aims.
This
argument for according rights to all human beings does seem to have a good
chance of success. For rational agents choosing moral principles to govern
their behaviour should of course pay attention to the ways in which those
principles might be distorted or abused. If the argument has a weakness,
however, it lies in its empirical assumption - namely, that a rule according
direct rights only to rational agents would be likely to be abused in such a
way as to undermine itself. For provided that all understand the theoretical
basis of the rules, they will be fore-armed against abuse. Thus suppose it were
generally agreed that all rational agents have moral rights, and that those who
are not fully rational agents have rights in proportion to the extent of their
rational agency. Then the reply is obvious to anyone who tries to argue that
since babies do not have direct rights, and since there is no clear boundary
between infancy and normal adulthood, therefore there can be no direct moral
objection to the holocaust. It is that the gradual transition from infancy to
adulthood is at the same time the transition from not bearing moral rights, to
having them in full measure.
This
attempt to undermine the argument from a slippery slope fails in its turn,
however. For one of the facts that rational agents will know, is that most
people are not very deeply theoretical. They should therefore select moral
principles that will provide a stable and easily understood framework within
which ordinary people can debate questions of right and wrong. Seen in these
terms, a rule that accorded rights in proportion to degree of rational agency would be wide open to creeping abuse.
For to think and speak in terms that withhold moral rights from some human
beings is to invite people to try to draw yet further distinctions - for
example, withholding rights from those who are sexually or intellectually
deviant, or from those whose intelligence is low. So I conclude that our
slippery slope argument is indeed successful in according rights to all human
beings.
(It
is worth noting the differences between the argument sketched here, and Regans
superficially similar argument for treating human babies as if they had rights.[5]
Recall that for Regan, those who have moral rights are primarily those who are
subjects-of-a-life - that is, who have a sense of their own future and their
own past. He then realises that on such an account human babies, up to the age
of one, at least, will not count as having rights. His reply is that we should,
nevertheless, treat such babies as if
they had the same rights as everyone else, by way of encouraging a moral
climate in which the rights of individuals are taken seriously. The first point
to make about Regans proposal is that it does not succeed in according rights
to human babies. To say that we should treat babies as if they had rights is not the same as saying that they do have rights. Yet it is this stronger
conclusion that we were able to deliver by means of the slippery slope argument
outlined above. The second point is that it is, in any case, by no means clear
how Regans argument is supposed to go. That is, it is far from clear how
treating those who do not have rights as if they did have them would foster a
climate in which the rights of individuals are taken seriously. The only
obvious suggestion is that any moral system in which some human beings are
denied moral rights is liable, by creeping abuse, to lead to a situation in
which some of those who do have moral rights have their rights ignored. This
is, in effect, our slippery slope argument, only shorn of its contractualist
context. The very argument that for Regan leads to the conclusion that we
should treat all humans as if they
had rights, for a contractualist leads to the conclusion that they do have rights. This is, I think, to the
advantage of the latter.)
Would
a slippery slope argument for according direct moral rights to all human beings
at the same time rule out abortion? For there is no clear line between foetus
and baby, any more than there is a clear line between baby and adult. But in
fact the issues here are not the same. For one of the things that contracting
rational agents should consider seriously, in framing their rules, are the
natural responses of thought and feeling that antecede moral belief. (This
point will come to the fore in Chapter 7.) It is natural to be struck by the
suffering of senile old people or babies, in a way that both supports and is supported
by assigning direct rights to these groups. It is not so natural for us respond
similarly towards a foetus, however, especially in the early stages, unless we
already have prior moral beliefs about its status. A rule withholding moral
rights from foetuses, and hence permitting at least early abortions, may
therefore be quite easily defended against abuse. This will become clearer in
the chapter after next.
In
addition to the argument from a slippery slope outlined above, contractualists
have available one further argument for according moral standing to all human
beings. This is an argument from social stability. One thing that rational
contractors should certainly consider, in framing a basic set of principles, is
whether those principles would have the desired effect of facilitating stable,
co-operative, community. In this they should have regard, among other things,
to the known facts of human psychology. One such fact is that human beings are
apt to care as intensely about their offspring as they care about anything,
irrespective of age and intelligence. A rule withholding moral standing from
those who are very young, very old, or mentally defective is thus likely to
produce social instability, in that many people would find themselves psychologically
incapable of living in compliance with it.
It
might be replied that stability could equally well be achieved by a rule
requiring us to respect the legitimate concerns of others. Then all those
non-rational humans who are objects of love would receive protection after all,
out of respect for the feelings of those who love them. But this is inadequate.
It would only accord such humans the same protection as items of property. Just
as I am obliged not to damage or destroy your cherished Mercedes, so I should
be obliged not to damage or destroy your child. But such obligations may be
overridden in cases where more fundamental rights are at stake. Suppose, for
example, that your Mercedes blocks the entrance to a mine-shaft in which I have
become imprisoned. You have become accustomed to use the entrance as a garage
during the week, and I should face a five day wait to get out. Then I may
surely destroy the car if this is my only means of escape, no matter how much
you may care about it, and even though my life may be in no danger. In these
circumstances you would, surely, accept that I had acted reasonably. But no one
could bring themselves to accept with equanimity the destruction of their child
in a similar situation. The only way of framing rules that we can live with,
then, is to accord all human beings the same basic rights - that is to say,
moral standing.
A
reply from anthropology
In reply to both of the above arguments, it
may be objected that there have been many human societies that have not
accorded the same basic rights to all human beings, and yet that have been both
stable and in other respects civilized - no slippery slope was ever embarked
upon. There have been very many human communities in which infanticide has been
widely practiced as a means of population control, for example.[6]
Yet the members of these communities were in all other ways inclined to show at
least as much respect for human life as ourselves, and were tender and loving
towards those children who were allowed to survive. So, it may be claimed, it
is simply not true that a system of morality that only accords moral standing
to those human beings who are rational agents need in any way be
self-defeating, or have dire consequences.
This
objection fails, however, for a variety of reasons. First, all the communities
in which infanticide has been openly practiced have been traditional ones, with
the practices in question sanctioned by long-standing social custom, and often
by religious belief as well. Such methods of achieving social stability are no
longer available to us. In our modern world, moral rules have to be defensible
in the face of free and open discussion, without appeal to religious sanction.
In order to show that all human beings should be accorded the same basic rights,
I do not have to argue that a rule withholding moral standing from some human
beings would be disastrous in all circumstances. It is enough that it would be
disastrous for us.
Second,
almost all the communities in question were teetering on the edge of survival,
either existing in particularly harsh environmental conditions, or in areas
where productive land was in short supply. Infanticide was thus deemed
necessary to prevent general starvation, or to preserve the lives of older
children. It is, then, by no means obvious that these communities failed to
recognize the moral standing of human infants. Their acts of infanticide may
rather be assimilated to legitimate cases of killing in self preservation. Any
version of contractualism will surely allow such killing, as the following
example will make clear.
Suppose
that Doris and Diana are deep sea divers, whose diving bell has come adrift and
sunk to the bottom of an ocean trench. They are told by radio that they cannot
hope to be rescued for at least twelve hours. They have only six hours of
oxygen remaining. So at least one of them must die. Now suppose, additionally,
that Diana in any case depends for her survival upon Doris (just as a human
infant depends for its survival upon adults) - perhaps she needs Doris to
administer a life-saving injection after ten hours, that she cannot administer
herself. In these circumstances it is surely permissible that Doris should kill
Diana in order that she herself may survive. While it may be admirable of Doris
if she were to volunteer to die along with Diana, this cannot be morally
required of her. That she should be prepared to kill in these circumstances
need not mean denying that Diana has moral standing or, indeed, violating her
rights. For rational contractors ought surely to allow that in those rare cases
where all will die unless one is killed, it is legitimate to preserve oneself.
Then so, too, in the case of infanticidal communities - their actions may be
consistent with according full moral standing to infants.
The
third reason why the anthropological evidence fails to undermine the slippery
slope and social stability arguments outlined earlier, involves a distinction
between the general virtues of justice and beneficence, which is in any case
central to contractualism, as we shall see in Chapter 7. (Justice has to do
with duties of non-interference, beneficence with attachment to the welfare of
others.) Suppose that human infants are accorded full moral standing, on a par
with normal adults. Then the fact that they are incapable of surviving on their
own means that the actions necessary to keep them alive are required by
beneficence rather than justice. It need not infringe a persons rights if we
fail to keep them alive, though it may display a serious lack of generosity on
our part. But in circumstances where the costs to us would be severe (as they
would be in most of the cases we are considering), our failure to keep alive
need not even show this. Recall the example of callous Carl from Chapter 2, who
failed to save the child drowning in a pond. His action would surely appear in
quite a different light if he were rushing his own child to hospital for an
emergency operation. That he fails to show beneficence towards the drowning
child in such circumstances involves no violation of right, nor need it involve
any sort of denial that the child has full moral standing. This example looks
entirely parallel to the cases of the infanticidal communities we have been
considering.
Since
the anthropological objection fails, I conclude that contractualists have at
least two successful strategies for according direct moral rights to all human
beings. The only problem still facing contractualism, therefore, is to get
closer to common-sense attitudes towards animals. For the intuition that Astrid
would act wrongly in using her cat as a dart-board is a powerful one. I shall
return to the matter in Chapter 7. First, I shall spend a chapter considering
the extent to which it is true that animals should not be counted as rational agents,
as I have been assuming up to now. For if it were to turn out that most animals
are rational agents after all, then reflective equilibrium would in any case
have been attained. Since it is clear that only prejudice can stand in the way
of assigning the same basic rights to all who are rational agents, we should
have found an explanation for why Astrid is wrong to throw darts at her cat.
Summary
No version of contractualism will accord moral standing to animals. There may, nevertheless, be indirect duties towards animals, owed out of respect for the legitimate concerns of animal lovers. But the protection thus extended to animals is unlikely to be very great. Nor can this approach explain the common-sense intuition that unmotivated cruelty to an animal is directly wrong. Contractualists also face the challenge of extending direct moral rights to those human beings who are not rational agents. While the first two avenues discussed, through which contractualists might hope to grant such rights, were seen to fail, two others - a slippery slope argument, and an argument from social stability - proved successful.
[1] See The Case for Animal Rights, ch. 5.4.
[2] This is made especially clear in Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical'.
[3] See A Theory of Justice, sect. 22.
[4] On this, see my Introducing Persons, chs. 7 & 8.
[5] See The Case for Animal Rights, pp. 319-20.
[6] See Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer, Should the Baby Live? (Oxford University Press, 1985), ch. 5.