Return to articles on cognitive architecture
Human creativity: its cognitive basis, its evolution, and its connections
with childhood pretence
Peter
Carruthers
ABSTRACT
This
paper defends two initial claims. First, it argues that essentially the same
cognitive resources are shared by adult creative thinking and problem-solving,
on the one hand, and by childhood pretend play, on the other¾namely,
capacities to generate and to reason with suppositions (or imagined
possibilities). Second, it argues that the evolutionary function of childhood
pretence is to practice and enhance adult forms of creativity. The paper goes
on to show how these proposals can provide a smooth and
evolutionarily-plausible explanation of the gap between the first appearance of
our species in Southern Africa some 100,000 years ago, and the creative
explosion of cultural, technological and artistic change which took place
within dispersed human populations some 60,000 years later. The intention of
the paper is to sketch a proposal which might serve as a guide for future
interdisciplinary research.
1 Introduction
2
Creativity and Pretence
3 Language
and Creativity
4 Language
and Cultural Accretions
5 Language,
Play and Model-Building
6 Creativity,
Protean Cognition and Sexual Selection
7 The
Evolution of Pretence
8 The
Emergence of Supposing
1 Introduction
Human beings are
unique in lots of ways, and human beings are especially smart in lots of ways.
We are capable of acquiring and retaining immense amounts of information over
the life-time of an individual; we are capable of learning and fine-tuning a
great many skills and new activities; and we are capable of using and
interpreting speech. But one of the most striking species-specific features of Homo sapiens sapiens, surely, is the
degree of creativity and innovation which we display in our
thought and behavior, both within the lives of individuals and across different
human cultures. This manifests itself in story-telling, in art, in the
construction of bodily ornaments and decorations, in humor, in religion-building,
in theory-construction, in problem-solving, in technological innovation, and in
myriad other ways.
Creativity, as I shall understand
it, will normally manifest itself in new types of behavior, going beyond mere
re-applications of established scripts or action-patterns. And creativity
itself is constituted, in part, by a capacity to combine together ideas in
novel ways in abstraction from any immediate environmental stimulation (see
section 2 below for further discussion). So a creature adopting a novel
solution to an environmental problem may be acting creatively, whereas one
which is merely applying an old solution in new circumstances (e.g. dipping for
ants with one sort of stick rather than another) will not be. And anyone who is
imagining how things could be other than they are will be thinking creatively,
whereas someone who thinks, The cat is vomiting purple liquid, in the
presence of a cat doing just that, will not be, even if they have never before entertained
a thought with that content. When applied as a predicate of individuals,
creative will be a matter of degree, of course¾a person or creature can be more or less
creative by engaging to a greater or lesser extent in creative behaviors and
creative thought-processes.
What
makes the distinctively-human degree of creativity possible? And how did our
creative capacity evolve? These are the two main questions to which I propose
to sketch answers in this paper. To elaborate on them a little (in reverse
order): Is our creativity a mere by-product of other selected-for traits (such
as our language-capacity, or bigger brains)? Or was it selected for in its own
right? And either way, what are its cognitive pre-requisites? That is to say,
what had to be in place within our cognition initially, which either provided
the sufficient conditions for our greatly enhanced creativity to make its
appearance, or which supplied the background against which some sort of
disposition to engage in creative activities could emerge or get selected for?
I
should emphasize that I only propose to sketch
answers to these questions in what follows, and to provide inconclusive¾but I hope plausible and suggestive¾arguments in support of those answers. In an
interdisciplinary and wide-ranging paper of this sort, it wont be possible to
deal with the issues thoroughly, and much of the needed evidence is in any case
lacking. My hope is to sketch out a framework for further enquiry, and to
render it just plausible enough to encourage others to pursue these questions
and to seek some of the necessary evidence from the standpoint of their own
interdisciplinary perspectives.
Any
account of the evolutionary origins of creativity has to be consistent with the
fossil record, of course. There is an emerging consensus that Homo sapiens sapiens first appeared some
100,000 years ago in Southern Africa. And there is evidence from about 90,000
years ago that this species was of basically modern intelligence, accumulating
knowledge about its environment and making a number of important technological
innovations; but that it was crucially lacking in creative imagination (Mithen
[1996]). Although the working of wooden artifacts may have undergone some
change, and bone tools were introduced for the first time, essentially the same
range of stone tools as had been employed by later sub-species of Homo erectus continued to be used
unchanged for tens of thousands of years. And there was little sign of the use
of body-ornaments and no sign of the production of art (and little evidence of
religion), until all these burst onto the scene (together with new stone-tool
industries) some 40,000 years ago on a world-wide basis (Stringer and Gamble
[1993]; Mithen [1996]).[1]
So far as we can tell from the
archaeological record, then, human creativity first manifested itself to any
significant degree about 40,000 years ago, continuing to emerge independently
around the globe over the next 10-15,000 years. (This is the so-called
creative explosion of the Upper Paleolithic period.) The question is, what
happened in the intervening 50,000-plus years from the first emergence of our
species? The puzzle is compounded by the fact that by the time of the creative
explosion human beings were already widely separated around the globe, and had
been so for at least 20,000 years (with Australia having been reached by boat
for the first time some 60,000 years ago). Yet this upsurge in human creativity
occurred more-or-less simultaneously around the world (give-or-take 10,000
years).
These facts set one of the central
puzzles which any account of the origins of creativity needs to address. It
looks as if we shall either have to
claim that human creativity resulted from a series of gradual
cognitive/cultural accumulations, independent of genetic change and built up
independently by different human communities over many millennia; or we shall need to claim that some
change occurred in the human genotype which could be selected for independently
of the nature of the ecological environment (as opposed to the universal
aspects of the social milieu). Yet neither of these alternatives looks
initially very plausible. For on either account, how are we to explain why the
relevant developments should have been constrained to take place in parallel
amongst dispersed human populations?[2]
In what follows I shall canvass a
number of possible explanations of human creativity, each of which carries
different implications for the cognitive underpinnings and likely evolution of
that capacity. These explanations will be assessed both for intrinsic
plausibility and for how successfully they can explain the 20,000-50,000 year gap between the geographical
dispersal of modern humans and the appearance of physical manifestations of
significant degrees of creativity in the fossil record. But these accounts will
also be assessed for the extent to which they can explain the connection
between adult creativity and childhood pretend play. This desideratum will be elaborated and defended in the next section.
2 Creativity and
Pretence
In addition to our
remarkable learning-capacities, linguistic abilities and creativity, another
salient species-specific fact about human beings is that the young of our
species engage extensively in pretend
play in infancy and childhood. From the age of about eighteen months all
normal children, in all human cultures, start to do something which (when
viewed from an external perspective, at least) appears very odd indeed they
begin to pretend. They engage in imaginary conversations with make-believe
characters (talking to a doll; inventing an imaginary companion) and they
pretend to be engaging in a wide variety of adult or fictional activities
(talking into a banana as if it were a telephone; pretending to cook and eat
mud pies; pretending to be a bird or an airplane). The young of no other
species of creature on earth behaves like this in natural circumstances not
even the other great apes (although adult hand-reared and language-trained
chimps have sometimes been observed to engage in activities which look very
much like pretence, at least; see
Jolly [1999]).
It
is hard to believe that these two species-specific properties¾adult creativity and childhood pretend play¾arent intimately connected with one another,
although it is true that they arent often discussed together.[3]
I shall argue in a moment that the two capacities can be seen as sharing
essentially the same cognitive basis, in so far as both involve exercises of
imagination. It will then be plausible that adult creativity in thought and
action is what childhood pretence is for.
(This will be yet another indicator of the importance of creativity as a
phenotypic property of human beings.) That is to say, it will appear likely
that the function of pretence should be to practice and enhance the kind of
creativity which acquires so much significance in our adult lives.
(This
should not be taken as a claim about childrens intentions, of course¾they arent trying
to turn themselves into creative adults. Rather, it should be seen as a
(tentative) claim about evolutionary and developmental function¾the idea is that children are pre-disposed to
engage in pretend play because this disposition helped their childhood
ancestors to become creative adults, which in turn caused the genes responsible
for that disposition to become general in the population.)
Although this suggestion needs to
be worked out (a task to which I shall return in a moment), it does at least
receive some preliminary support from comparative biology. For the young of all
mammalian species engage in just the kinds of play which serve to practice, and
are tailored towards, their distinctive adult behaviors. Thus kittens of all
species of cat will engage in the sort of play-stalking, play-jumping and
play-biting which will later be used when hunting; young male deer will take
part in the kind of head-butting which will later be used in the competition
for mates in the rut; the young of many prey species like gazelle engage in
play-leaping and play-running of just the sort needed to escape from predators;
and so on and so forth (Smith [1982]; Bekoff and Byers [1998]). By analogy,
then, if we ask what human pretend
play is for, the answer will be: its function is to practice for the sorts of
imaginative thinking which will later manifest themselves in the creative
activities of adults.
The connection between the two
forms of behavior, arguably, is that each involves essentially the same
cognitive underpinnings¾namely, a capacity to generate, and to reason
with, novel suppositions or imaginary
scenarios. When pretending, what a child has to do is to suppose that something is the case (that
the banana is a telephone; that the doll is alive), and then think and act
within the scope of that supposition (Perner [1991]; Jarrold et al. [1994a]; Harris [2000]; Nichols
and Stich [2000]).[4] Similarly,
when adults are engaged in the construction of a new theory, or are seeking a
novel solution to a practical problem, or are composing a tune, they have to
think: Suppose it were the case that P, or Suppose I did it like this, or Suppose it sounded like so. Given these commonalities, it does
then seem plausible that the young of our species should engage in
supposition-for-fun in childhood in order that they may be better able to
suppose-for-real when they reach adulthood.
After a fallow period extending
through much of the twentieth century, there is now an extensive psychological
literature on the subject of human creativity. (See, for example, Langley et al. [1987]; Sternberg [1988], [1999];
Boden [1992], [1994]; Finke et al.
[1992]; Weisberg [1993]; Smith et al.
[1995]; and Amabile [1996].) Much of this has concentrated on what might be
called successful creativity or influential creativity, studied by
examining the lives and circumstances of famous innovators in the arts,
sciences and business worlds. As a consequence, those taking this approach tend
to emphasize such factors as extensive background knowledge or training and
high levels of intrinsic motivation in their analyses of creativity. For
these qualities are shared almost universally by those who have succeeded in
making a significant contribution to their chosen field of activity.
My interest, however, is in the
universal cognitive underpinnings of normal (often mundane) human creativity,
rather than in the qualities of character, motivation, or prior knowledge of
those who excel in this respect. And here the two most important factors¾whose relevance is acknowledged by all parties¾are some sort of capacity to generate new
ideas, on the one hand (e.g. by noticing a novel analogy), together with
abilities to see and to develop the significance of those ideas, on the other.
These factors are certainly accorded a fundamental role in one of the
influential psychological accounts which is explicitly designed as a theory of
universal cognitive creativity, the so-called geneplore (for generate and
explore) model of creativity developed by Finke and colleagues.
According to Finke et al., creative cognition involves two
distinct stages. First, there is the generation of a novel hypothesis or idea¾which at this stage is merely entertained rather than believed or
endorsed¾and then there is the exploration of that idea, developing it and
working out its consequences, before finally accepting it or putting it into
practice. (See Finke et al. [1992];
Finke [1995]; Ward et al. [1999].)
This two-stage account maps
remarkably smoothly onto our best accounts of pretend play. An episode of
pretence will begin with an initial supposition or imagined scenario¾that the banana is a telephone; that the
teddy-bears are having a tea party; and so on. The child then acts as if that
supposition were true, following familiar scripts and/or drawing inferences
appropriate to its truth in the light of their background knowledge¾making dialing movements, say, or setting out
the tea cups and saucers (Harris [2000]; Nichols and Stich [2000]). Often, too,
yet further suppositions will be introduced into the play-episode, serving to
elaborate and extend the pretence¾for example, supposing that Granny has answered
the phone-call and hence beginning to talk to her; or supposing that there is
cake to set out with the tea as well.
I shall return to the connections between
creativity and pretence when proffering a positive account of their evolution
in later sections. For the moment I conclude that it should be a constraint on
theories of the evolution of our capacity for creative thought and action that
they should proceed, at least in part, by explaining the evolutionary emergence
of childhood pretend play. At any rate, it seems reasonable to take this as an
initial working hypothesis, worthy of further exploration.
I shall turn, now, to canvass a
range of different proposals which have been made concerning the evolution of
human creative capacities. This discussion will, of necessity, be extremely
brisk, serving mostly to motivate and set up my own thesis to be advanced in
later sections.
Some people have claimed that possession of a
fully-syntactic natural language is sufficient for the emergence of normal
human creativity (Noble and Davidson [1996]). Those holding this view believe
two things. First, they think that natural language is the vehicle for
characteristically human thought and reasoning. And second, they think that the
flexibility, recursive power, and creative potential of natural languages are
what underpin the creativity of human thought and imagination. I am sympathetic
towards the first of these claims, and have elsewhere argued that natural
language sentences may be the vehicles of conscious propositional thinking
(Carruthers [1996a], [1998b]; see also Mithen [1996]); and it is a claim for
which powerful independent psychological evidence has now begun to emerge
(Hermer-Vazquez et al. [1999]).
Moreover, I shall suggest in section 8 below that there is an element of truth
in the second claim as well.
In
addition, it might be claimed that this account can mesh nicely with the
developmental data, since the appearance of pretend play at about eighteen
months of age coincides with the language spurt of extensive vocabulary
acquisition. But this claim does not bear closer examination, for the proposal
is that it is specifically syntax
which is responsible for creative thinking, not just vocabulary. But
eighteen-month infants have little grasp of natural language syntax, and their
productions are confined to one or two-word unstructured utterances. Now, it
may well be the case that infants comprehension of syntax outstrips their
productive abilities, and it might be claimed that it is the former which is
specifically implicated in imaginative thought. (It is true of development in
general that comprehension precedes production.) But it is actually doubtful
whether infants understanding of syntax is advanced enough to do the job
required (Locke [1993]).
The real problem with this
approach, however, is that (in view of the archaeological record) it is obliged
to claim that language appeared very late on the evolutionary scene - circa
40,000 years ago, in fact. But given the geographical separation of different
sub-groups of the human species well before the time when we first have
significant evidence of human creativity, this account then seems required to
postulate either that an innate language-faculty
evolved in parallel amongst distinct groups of humans at about the same time, or that there is no innate
language-faculty, and that languages are acquired using general-learning
principles. Neither of these options is at all attractive.
Noble and Davidson ([1996]) opt for the latter
alternative. Their view is that language is but one manifestation of a sort of
generalized symbolic capacity (other manifestations of which include
paintings and tribal totems), which is underpinned by general intelligence, and
which is to be understood in behavioristic rather than cognitive terms. (Noble
and Davidson cite Ryle [1949] and Wittgenstein [1953] in their support.) This
flies in the face of the Chomskian thesis that humans possess an innately channeled
and informationally-structured language faculty (e.g. Chomsky [1988], [1995]),
which is powerfully supported by a variety of different kinds of consideration
(Pinker [1994]). But in any case it remains extremely puzzling that symbolic
behaviors should have first made their appearance at about the same time
world-wide, since the degree of geographical separation involved seems to rule
out transmission by learning.
The alternative is that there is an innately-channeled language
faculty, but that it evolved independently in geographically separated groups
of humans. But this is no less implausible. First, this is because the language
capacities of contemporary humans are near-enough identical; and all human
natural languages are equivalent in terms of their basic expressive power
(Pinker [1994]). Second, it is because the adaptations necessary to underpin
language, on any nativist approach, are subtle and various¾there needed to be physical adaptations to the
mouth and larynx to facilitate the smooth production of speech; there were
physical adaptations to the auditory system to enable speech to be processed
independently of other sound; and there were a suite of language-specific
cognitive adaptations for syntax, semantics and phonology, probably dividing
into distinct production and comprehension systems (Pinker [1994]). It is
beyond belief that a system of this complexity should have evolved similarly in
isolated groups of humans, despite the wide variations in ecological challenges
to which those groups would have been subject, and the differences in the
social arrangements which they would have enjoyed.
I conclude, then, that the thesis
that language is fully sufficient for human creativity is implausible. It will
have to be claimed, rather, that something in addition to language was needed
for distinctive human creative behaviors to make their appearance.
On some accounts, possession of a
fully-syntactic natural language is necessary but not sufficient for human
creativity. These theories allow that full-blown human language (as opposed to
the sort of a-syntactic proto-language used by two year-old children, which
may also have been used by the Neanderthals and by Archaic forms of Homo sapiens) first appeared with the evolution
of anatomically modern humans some 100,000 years ago in Southern Africa. What
then had to happen between that time and the creative explosion of c.40,000
years ago was either that the good
trick of almost-continuous auto-stimulation (talking to oneself) had to be
discovered and catch on (Dennett [1991], [1995]; Bickerton [1995]); or that material culture had to develop
to a sufficient extent to support creative activities (Sperber [1996]; Mithen
[1998], [2000]). But both views at least agree that the emergence of human
creativity depended upon a set of cultural accretions, in addition to language.
Dennetts
view is now well-known. Language first evolved as a medium for communication
and public negotiation; but then some of our ancestors discovered that by
asking themselves questions they could elicit information which they did not
know that they had, and that by issuing themselves commands they could induce
desirable behaviors. This good trick gradually caught on and spread, and
became internalized, eventually giving rise to what Dennett calls the Joycean
machine¾the stream of inner verbalization and imagery which radically altered
the computational powers of the human brain, and which gave rise to the
indefinite flexibility and creativity of modern human intelligence.
This
account faces essentially the same difficulties as the claim that language
itself is a cultural accretion, discussed in section 3 above. First, it is
puzzling how the Joycean machine could have acquired basically the same form in
geographically dispersed groups of humans by about the same time. This problem
is further compounded by the second difficulty, which is that we lack any clear
mechanism of transmission. The good trick of auto-stimulation is supposed to
be just that¾a learned behavior. But it is mysterious how children are supposed to
acquire it. No one ever tells them
that it would be a good idea to engage in inner speech; and nor, of course, can
they copy such behavior from observation of others. So it is by no means
obvious how the Joycean machine is supposed to be transmitted down the
generations. Nor is it clear how it could spread around the globe by contacts
between adults. (Are we to imagine that hunter-gatherers from different tribes
meeting at a water-hole would think to tell
one another that self-directed speech is a useful activity?)
In addition, Dennetts view cannot
really make out a satisfactory connection between adult human creativity and
childhood pretend play. For while it is true that young children will often
talk aloud to themselves while they engage in problem-solving activities¾which can plausibly be thought of as the
precursor of inner speech (and hence of the creation of the Joycean machine)¾such talk emerges substantially later than the
first appearance of pretend play at eighteen months (Diaz and Berk [1992]). So
it can hardly be the case that pretend play (like creative thinking generally,
on this account) is made possible by the internalization of speech.
The alternative form of cultural accretion
account of creativity emphasizes accumulations of material culture¾particularly artifacts and/or enduring public
symbols. In one version, what had to accumulate were semi-permanent
externalizations of mentality, like paintings, statues, and notched-bone
calendars (Mithen [1998], [2000]). But it is hard to believe that these could
have been sufficient to give rise to creative cognition (let alone to pretend
play).
Mithen ([1996], [1998]) does make
out a strong case that what we see emerging in the fossil record for the first
time c.40,000 years ago is concrete evidence of what he calls cognitive
fluidity¾namely, the linking together of ideas across two or more cognitive
domains or modules. We see figures which are half-human half-animal; the
transformation of natural objects into bodily ornaments; ritual burial
(suggestive of belief in after-life, which would involve a cross-over between
the biological and mental domains); and the specialization of hunting-weapons
for different kinds of game. But this evidence is equally consistent with what
will be my own proposal, that inter-modular transfer became possible with the
evolution of language c.100,000 years ago, and that what was lacking until much
more recently was the development of creative imagination. Whereas it is, in
contrast, far from clear how an accumulation of material culture could
facilitate creative thought.[5]
A more plausible hypothesis might
be that it was accumulations of wealth (in the form of skills and improved
tools, at least) which provided our ancestors with the free time in which to be creative (Sperber [1996]). On this
account, the capacity for creativity
was fully there from the advent of language 100,000 years ago; but it took a
good many further millennia for humans to start using that capacity for
anything other than practical problem-solving.
This is certainly a possible view.
And it could actually be combined with most elements of the account which I
favor (see sections 7-9 below), according to which a disposition
towards pretend play was selected for in order to enhance adult creativity¾only with the dates for this pushed back by
60,000 years or so to the first emergence of Homo sapiens sapiens. One significant problem with the view,
however, is that it was not just frivolous products like bead necklaces,
cave-paintings, and ritual burials which underwent a revolution in the Upper
Paleolithic; it was also the stone-tool industries (Mithen [1996]). The puzzle
is that these shouldnt have undergone development earlier, if practical
creative intelligence had been fully operative then.
According to Harris ([2000]), in contrast, the
function of pretend play is to provide practice in mental-model building,
essential for comprehension of discourse about the not-here-and-now. For in
pretence what a child has to do is build on and elaborate their initial
supposition into a more complete model
of the imagined situation, drawing on relevant portions of their background
knowledge; and in discourse comprehension, too, there is an extensive
literature documenting the importance of mental-model building for successful
understanding. In which case Harris may have to say that what occurred c.40,000
years ago was a leap forward in linguistic as well as in imaginative
capacities.[6]
Would this commit him to claiming
that full-blown language only made its appearance then, too? Probably not.
Harris can allow that grammatical language was in place from the first
appearance of Homo sapiens sapiens
100,000 years ago, and even that these humans had the capacity to talk about
the not-here-and-now. He would just need to say that they werent very good at
the latter. Before 40,000 years ago, humans could talk and comprehend
effectively in relation to the here and now, but their abilities beyond that
might have been slow and halting. What the drive towards pretend play in
childhood then gave us, was practice in the construction of mental models,
which then in turn enabled testimony in relation to the not-here-and-now to be
much more effective.
The idea, then, is that the
mental-model building involved in childhood pretence is practice for, and
enhances, the sort of mental-model building necessary for text and discourse
comprehension. As Harris rightly points out, this would not be a plausible evolutionary
suggestion if we maintain the parallel strictly, and concentrate on adult
comprehension of fictional discourse.
(Or at least, not unless we were to buy into some story about runaway sexual
selection - maybe males displayed to females by telling stories to them? See Miller
[2000], for some suggestions along these lines.) So his actual proposal is that
pretence helps with testimony. By building mental models of the non-actual in
pretence, children are facilitated in their understanding of testimony about
the not-here-and-now, which requires them similarly to construct a mental model
of the described situation.
One worry about this idea is that pretence
takes us one further remove from the actual situation than does testimony about
distant events¾it takes us, not just out of the actual current
situation, but out of the actual world (considered as including distant parts
of space and time). Why would we need to practice anything so radical in order
to gain the desired benefit¾namely, the capacity to construct mental models
of the (presumed) actual world, albeit models of spatially or temporally
distant parts of it? To put the point another way, why do children engage in
pretence as opposed to sustained recollection of their pasts (requiring them to
build and elaborate on mental models of actual events), or sustained
speculation about distant ones?
Another problem is that it is far from clear
why increased efficiency and flexibility in information-exchange (testimony)
should lead to an explosion in the use of art and body-ornamentation. Why would
an increased capacity to talk about past, future, or spatially-distant events
express itself in cave-painting or the construction of bead necklaces? The
connection is not perspicuous, to say the least.[7]
(Though again, Harris might appeal to some version of the cultural accretions
accounts by way of defense.)
I think that Harris functional
speculation misses the key piece of information about pretence, in fact¾namely, that pretending is a kind of supposing. To pretend that P is to
suppose that P for fun, roughly speaking. And sustained episodes of pretence
are best understood as episodes of thinking and reasoning within the scope of a
supposition.[8]
And if we ask what supposition is
for, or what role it plays in our adult lives, the answer is pretty obvious, I
suggest¾it is a crucial tool in both practical and theoretical thinking. As
practical agents we reason from suppositions all the time: Suppose I did this;
what would then happen? What could I then do or get? And so on. As
knowledge-seekers, too, suppositions play a crucial role. Without a capacity to
suppose, neither science nor technological innovation would be possible, except
on a trial-and-error basis. The main problem with Harris proposal concerning
the function of pretence, then, is that it breaks the very-plausible connection
between pretence and adult creative thinking and reasoning. For pretence is not
for creativity but for testimony, on this account.
Yet another proposal is made by Miller ([1997],
[2000]). On this view, too, possession of fully-syntactic language may have
been necessary, but was not sufficient for the emergence of human creativity.
Creative cognition was additionally selected for, resulting from the sexual
choices of both males and females, as a reliable indicator of reproductive
fitness in general, and also as an indicator of protean cognition in particular. The claim, in effect, is that
human creativity is our peacocks tail¾a sexually-selected fitness-indicator. This is
a complex proposal, which will require some unpacking before it can be
evaluated.
Miller
([2000]) makes out a very plausible case for the importance of sexual selection
in evolution generally (although its significance is frequently overlooked by
those who are not working biologists), arguing that it is often the main
driving force behind the divergence of species. Throughout most of the animal
kingdom sexual selection operates particularly upon males, since it is males
who must compete for access to the limiting resource of female reproductive
capacity, while it is females who must choose from amongst the competitors. But
in pair-bonding species such as our own, sexual choice can operate on both
sexes. For in so far as males are to commit their reproductive resources to one
female, then they, too, will need mechanisms to ensure that they select wisely.
In
general, sexually selected traits need to be reliable indicators of fitness. In
consequence they tend to be costly to produce, hard to maintain, and to be
highly sensitive to the presence of genetic mutations. (All are true of the
peacocks tail.) Miller points out that displays of human creativity (in humor,
in story-telling, and in status-enhancing activity generally) satisfy at least
the first two of these requirements, being dependent, as they are, on the
healthy functioning and distinctive size of the human brain. For our brains
take many years to grow to maturity, and are extremely costly to maintain in
terms of their energy requirements (accounting for 40% of the bodys glucose
consumption, for example). In addition, Miller thinks, there was probably
sexual selection in hominids for honest advertisements of protean cognition, of which the most obvious are partly-random
displays of creative thought. And if creativity is being selected for, then
there will be selection for anything¾such as childhood pretend play¾which serves to enhance it. So the connection
between adult creativity and childhood pretend play can be adequately
explained.
Miller ([1997], [2000]) argues that there would
have been powerful selective pressures acting on socially-competitive
mind-readers to make themselves genuinely unpredictable in certain kinds of
competitive situation. Consider an alpha-male primate concerned to protect his
access to the females of the troupe, for example. What strategy should he adopt
in response to challenges to his authority? One option is to punish each and
every transgression, large or small. But this would be very costly in terms of
both time and energy. Another option is to set a threshold in the spectrum of
potential challenges, below which challenges are ignored, but above which they
are punished. The trouble with this strategy, however, is that the other males
will rapidly learn what the threshold is, and so will know that they can flout
his authority with impunity below it.
A better strategy than either of
the above¾and which Miller dubs Mad Dog¾is unpredictability. (Note that this strategy
is actually observed in nature, in these sorts of circumstances, amongst both
apes and human despots.) The alpha-male will only punish some transgressions (thus minimizing the costs to himself), but it
will be unpredictable which ones he
will punish, or how frequently. He thereby provides a powerful incentive
against any transgression, while at
the same time spreading uncertainty amongst his competitors. And the best way
for him to be able to do this is if he can somehow make his responses genuinely
random, or protean, in such a way
that they cannot be predicted even by himself.
In fact Miller makes out a powerful
case that alongside the selection pressures building mind-reading abilities in
primates and hominids, and developing in tandem with them, there would have
been pressures for hominid cognition to become protean in a variety of competitive conditions.[9]
With a capacity for protean unpredictability becoming closely linked to
reproductive success, there might have been a further pressure¾this time in the form of sexual selection¾in favor of honest
displays of proteanism. And this might then have manifested itself in
various forms of human creativity, and in a valuing of novelty.
But what of the time-scales
involved in this proposal? How can Miller handle the 60,000 year gap before the
creative explosion of the Upper Paleolithic? He could claim that what happened between the advent of language
c.100,000 years ago and the creative explosion of c.40,000 years ago was a
genotypic change resulting from sexual selection, which could thus have
occurred in a manner which was independent of the different environmental
conditions experienced by geographically dispersed groups of humans. Against
this, however, is the point that sexual selection in dispersed groups tends to
result in between-group differences in the sexually selected traits, since
small initial disparities in the initial preferences become greatly amplified
over time. (Note that sexually-selected human bodily traits - such as body hair, as well as breast, buttock
and penis size - do
vary significantly between different human groups.) But there is no evidence of
between-group differences in creativity.
As a result, what Miller ([2000])
actually does is deny the reality of the gap between the first appearance of
our species and the emergence of creative behaviors. He joins those who wish to
claim that the appearance of such a gap is a mere artifact of a variety of
factors conspiring to hide the evidence of earlier forms of creativity from us.
This is certainly a possible position; and he may well turn out to be right.
But my project in this paper is to see what can be done if we take the
existence of the creativity gap seriously, and attempt to accommodate it
(rather than deny it) in our accounts of the emergence of distinctive human
creativity. Accordingly, from this perspective, Millers proposal is not an
acceptable one.
On the view that I favor, and which has begun
to emerge from the above discussion, all of the cognitive pre-requisites for
creative thought were in place from the first emergence of anatomically modern
humans. What then happened between that time and c.40,000 years ago was that
there was selection for a childhood disposition towards pretend play. The
cognitive pre-requisites for pretence were in place from at least the advent of
language, I suggest; but actually engaging
in frequent pretend play in childhood served to practice and enhance our
imaginative abilities.
Why was this selected for? Not, I
suppose, because exercises of imagination are an indicator of protean
cognition; but rather because they are partially constitutive of intelligence, in the sense of general
problem-solving abilities. But the selection-pressure can still have been
sexual (operating equally between the sexes) rather than environmental, just as
Miller ([2000]) argues; or it could just as well have been environmental; or it
could have been both of these operating together. On any of these three
alternatives there will be no particular problem in explaining the co-evolution
of pretend play in dispersed populations.
If the selection pressure for
pretend play was sexual, we just have to suppose that early humans had the
capacity to discern the connection between imaginative abilities and
problem-solving success. This seems perfectly plausible, since everyone is
agreed that these humans would have had highly-developed forms of causal
understanding, as well as fully modern mind-reading abilities, in addition to
language. Then children who happened to be more disposed to engage in pretend
play in childhood would grow up to become more imaginative/intelligent adults;
and this quality would then be perceived and valued by potential mating
partners of the opposite sex, leading to greater reproductive success.
Note that one important difference
between this proposal and that of Miller ([2000]) is that the preference for
creative partners need not itself be innate, but results rather from the human
capacity to detect the causal connection between creative thinking, on the one
hand, and problem-solving success, on the other. There is therefore no reason
to think that small initial differences in this preference between dispersed
populations would have been consistent enough to amplify over time, leading to
significant differences in creative abilities between different human groups.
Consistent with this hypothesis, a large cross-cultural study of patterns of
human mate-preference found that in all of the 37 cultures studied, both men
and women rated intelligence high amongst the desirable characteristics of a
potential mate (Buss [1989]).[10]
Alternatively, we might think that pretend play
was selected for because those who engaged in it (or who engaged in it more)
subsequently proved more successful in problem solving (and so in surviving and
reproducing) when they reached adulthood. Since what was being enhanced here is
a creative problem-solving capacity which can operate across wide variations in
environment, the fact of such variation need provide no obstacle to parallel
selection. Or in addition (and perhaps most plausibly) both reproductive and
environmental pressures might have operated at once.
What sort of cognitive architecture would have
had to be in place 100,000 years ago, on this account? On the model of pretence
proposed by Nichols and Stich ([2000]), humans would have needed two distinct
cognitive elements. First, they would have needed a supposition-generator, or
supposer, to create representations of imagined possibilities.[11]
And second, humans would have needed a possible worlds box, which is a memory
system designed to store suppositions and their elaborations during the course
of a pretend-episode.
Now, I doubt whether there is any
reason to think that the possible worlds box required the creation of any new
adaptation. Surely, already-existing working-memory systems could have been
co-opted for the job. But the supposition-generator is another matter. For on
this model it looks as if it would have required the creation of a whole new
type of propositional attitude (distinct from either belief or desire, nor
reducible to combinations thereof) in order for imaginative thinking and/or
pretend play to make its appearance in the hominid lineage. This might then be
taken to suggest that it would have required some powerful selectional pressure
in order for imaginative thinking to become possible. But actually there is
some reason to think that imagination comes in at least two forms, each of
which would be provided for free by the evolution of other faculties. Let me
briefly elaborate.
First,
there is experiential imagination¾namely, the capacity to form and manipulate
images relating to a given sense modality (visual, auditory, and so on). There
is some reason to think that a basic capacity for this sort of imagination is a
by-product of the conceptualizing processes inherent in the various perceptual
input-systems. There are extensive feed-back neural pathways in the visual
system, for example, which are used in object-recognition when asking
questions of ambiguous or degraded input. And these very pathways are then
deployed in visual imagination so as to generate quasi-perceptual inputs to the
visual system (Kosslyn [1994]). Evidence from cognitive archaeology (concerning
the imposition of sophisticated symmetries on stone tools, which would have
required a capacity to visualize and manipulate an image of the desired
product) suggests that this capacity would have been present at about 400,000 years
before the present (Wynn [2000])¾i.e. considerably before the evolution of
full-blown language, if the latter only appeared some 100,000 years ago, as
many believe.
Second,
there is propositional imagination.
This is the capacity to form and consider a propositional representation
without commitment to its truth or desirability. There is some reason to think
that this capacity comes to us for free too, this time with language. For a
productive language system will involve a capacity to construct new sentences,
whose contents are as yet neither believed nor desired, which can then serve as
objects of reflective consideration of various sorts. In which case a capacity
for propositional imagination is likely to have formed a part of the normal
human cognitive endowment for about at least the last 100,000 years.
Of
course a mere capacity for creative generation of new sentences (or images)
will not be sufficient for imaginative thinking as we normally understand it.
For there is nothing especially imaginative about generating any-old new
sentence or image. Rather, we think imagination consists in the generation of relevant and/or fruitful and interesting new ideas. And such a capacity will not
come to us for free with anything. But then this is precisely the
developmental function of pretend play, on the present proposal¾through frequent practice, to help build a
consistent disposition to generate novel suppositions which will be both relevant and interesting.
In any case the supposer neednt be an additional
cognitive faculty, with any distinct neural realization. It just has to be the
possibility of taking a distinct (non-judgmental, non-evaluative) attitude towards contents¾namely, the
attitude of supposing. But, arguably,
we get this attitude for free with imagery and language. What these faculties
give us is the capacity to frame and then consider a possibility (represented
by a visual image, say, or by a new sentence), without yet endorsing,
rejecting, or desiring it. Once we have this, we effectively have the capacity
to suppose.
So both pretend play and creative
adult thinking would have been possible
from around 100,000 years ago, I suggest. But it then took some 50-60,000 years for a strong disposition towards
pretend play in childhood to become established in the human phenotype, thus
leading to greatly enhanced creative thought and behavior amongst adults as
well, and hence leading to the Upper Paleolithic creative explosion.
What is the source of childrens disposition
towards pretend play, however? Is it possible to say more about the mental
mechanism which produces and rewards the activity of supposing? In Carruthers
([1996b]) I suggested that children are wired up so as to detect, and then
receive intrinsic gratification from, acts of supposition as such. This account
was intended to explain the absence
of pretend play in children with autism¾a condition which I assume (following Leslie
[1993], and Baron-Cohen [1995]) to be a kind of mind-blindness resulting from
damage to a developing mind-reading module. For although autistic children
rarely engage in pretence spontaneously, they do appear to retain the capacity for it, and can generate
pretend episodes when prompted to do so¾they just dont normally do it because they
dont see the point (Lewis and Boucher [1988]; Jarrold et al. [1994b]). My suggestion was therefore that it might be the
supposition-detector which is damaged in autism, where this detector can be
thought of as an element in the normal mind-reading system.
The
problem with this account, however, is that it attributes precocious
mind-reading abilities to normal eighteen month-olds (as Nichols and Stich
[2000] correctly point out). There is plenty of evidence that such children
have a developing understanding of agency, and of desire and perception as
non-intentional relations between agents and objects (Wellman [1990]; Gopnik
and Melzoff [1997]). But there is also powerful evidence that children under
three do not have any conception of
mental states as such, considered as subjective representational states of the
agent, which may represent objects partially or incorrectly (Wellman [1990];
Perner [1991]). So it seems unlikely that an eighteen month-old infant would be
capable of representing its own state of pretending, as such.
A better proposal is that the
rewards for pretence derive from engagement with, and quasi-satisfaction of,
the agents first-order goals and interests. For notice that imagination in
general seems to be connected up with the appetitive and motivational systems
in something very like the way that belief is, as Harris ([2000]) demonstrates
at length. As is familiar, imagined sex can make you feel sexy, imagined
insults can make you angry, imagined food can make your mouth water, and so on.
This is the basis of the enjoyment we take in story-telling, cinema, and works
of fiction¾imagining doing and experiencing interesting things is itself
interesting.
The satisfactions to be derived
from pretend play are essentially the same, I suggest. Suppose that you find
telephones fascinating, as young children often do (they are of manifest
importance to adults, but eighteen month-olds are rarely allowed to use them);
and suppose that you also like to talk to your granny. Then by imagining that the
banana is a telephone, and by representing yourself as making a call, you can
gain some of the motivational rewards of the real thing; as you can by
imagining that your granny has answered and is there to be talked to. Ditto for imaginary friends, making mud
pies, and pretending to be a bird or an airplane.
This proposal still leaves us in a
position to explain why autistic children dont normally engage in pretend
play, however, despite having the capacity to do so. We just have to suppose,
first, that such children will have a weakened or damaged conception of agency,
resulting from the delayed or damaged development of their mind-reading module;
and second, that enjoyment of pretence requires the capacity to represent ones
own agency. Let me try to substantiate these points in turn.
The first point is easy, since it
is well-established that autistic infants lack a normal sense of agency.
Indeed, amongst the most reliable diagnostic criteria for autism in young
children are a tendency to treat other people as objects (using adults as mere items of furniture; leading adults by
the hand and then pushing their hands in the direction of a desired object),
and an absence of shared-attention behaviors (lack of pointing and social
referencing; a failure to read and react appropriately to behavioral cues such
as eye-direction; and so on). Even if all children at the age of two will lack
any conception of their own and others mental states as such, normal children
will, and autistic children do not, have a robust conception of themselves and
others as agents, and routinely represent the goal-directed nature of the
actions of those agents (Baron-Cohen [1995]; Gopnik and Melzoff [1997]).
To see the second point that
enjoyment of pretence requires a capacity to represent ones own agency think
again of the child using a banana as a telephone. The child is not actually
making a telephone call, of course; so there is nothing in the movements which
she makes, as such, to engage with her desire to do so. In order to gain any
satisfaction, the child must represent the movements of her finger while she
stabs at the banana as an act of
dialing; and she must represent the movements involved in putting the banana to
her ear as the act of holding a
telephone in such a way as to hear and be heard; and so on. This surely
requires a capacity to categorize bodily movements as goal-directed actions¾which is just the capacity which autistic
infants appear to lack.
I have explained how the rewards
for pretence derive from the connections between our motivational systems and
imagination in general; and I have explained why those rewards may not be
available to mind-blind autistic children. But now it might begin to look as
if I have explained too much. For the rewards for pretence (as well as the
capacity for it) now also appear to emerge as a mere by-product of other
faculties. In which case the gap which I supposed to exist between the
appearance of the capacity for
pretence and for creative thought 100,000 years ago and the emergence of a
regular disposition to engage in it
will disappear.
But actually, we still need to
explain why children should ever start
to pretend in the first place. The above discussion only purported to explain
why they should continue to do so once they begin. So what may have developed
between the first emergence of our species and the creative explosion of
c.40,000 years ago is a strong childhood disposition to generate new
suppositions, and a disposition to begin thinking and acting within the scope of
those suppositions. This disposition, once activated, would yield its own
rewards through the connections between imagination and the motivational
system. And its regular activation would serve to practice for adult uses of
supposition in theory-building and problem-solving.[12]
My account might seem to be subject to (at
least) the following two objections. Seeing how these objections can be
answered will lead to further clarification and elaboration of my proposals.
First,
how is it that the account isnt vulnerable to one of the objections raised
against Harris proposal in section 5 above (the proposal, namely, that
pretence is to enhance our comprehension of discourse about the
not-here-and-now)? For pretending can take us, not just outside of the actual
situation, but outside of the real world. Pretence can be mere fantasy. But if
pretence is for enhancing our problem-solving abilities, this might seem
puzzling. For such abilities are always exercised in, and tied to the parameters
of, some real situation.
This
objection is relatively easy to answer, however. For it is no part of my story
that creative thinking is only useful in practical reasoning about known
aspects of the real world. On the contrary, it is equally valuable in enabling
us to generate novel explanations and hypotheses, about the unseen causes of
observed events, say. Such hypotheses are distinguished from fantasy only in
being directed at the real world. In
other respects they can take us entirely outside of the world of our prior
knowledge or experience, just as can fantasy. For example, hunters tracking a
wounded animal will often have to generate highly speculative hypotheses in
order to interpret the subtle signs they observe - a capacity which bears striking resemblances
to the sort of creative thinking which goes on in hypothesis-generation in
contemporary science (Liebenberg [1990]; Carruthers [2002]).
The
second and more challenging objection is this. If the selection-pressure which
led to a childhood disposition to engage in pretend play had to do with
enhancing imaginative thinking in adulthood, as I claim, then it is puzzling
that what should have resulted is a disposition to play (involving overt movements) rather than to fantasize. Why
waste energy (and sometimes risk injury!) by pretending to be a bird, if merely
imagining being a bird would have served the developmental purpose just as
well?
One sort of answer might be that,
at the age when pretend-play first starts to emerge, young children do not have
the sort of introspective access to their own mental states which would be
necessary for enjoyment of mere imagination (Gopnik [1993]; Carruthers
[1996b]). But this would really only defer the problem. For why is it then
crucial that imagination-enhancing activity should begin at eighteen months
rather than later in development, given that imagination will only begin to
enhance fitness considerably later?
A
much more plausible answer can be arrived at by noticing that play activity¾e.g. of a rough-and-tumble sort¾would almost certainly have existed already in
the repertoire of human infants, just as it does in the infancy of all other
mammals. Then as so often happens in evolution, this pre-existing disposition
may have become harnessed to serve the development of creativity, with a
disposition to engage in play
activity now becoming a disposition to engage in pretend activity. And there may well then have been selection
pressures sufficient to prevent the attenuation of any overt active component
(perhaps also combined with a shift to later in development, in light of the
point made in the previous paragraph). For example, overt pretence can easily
become shared pretence, which would not only have benefits for the development
of the mind-reading faculty, but can also be useful in building alliances and
honing social skills generally. Moreover, by combining pretence with activity,
children can continue to develop the sorts of physical skills (e.g. involved in
controlling and manipulating objects) which will also be useful in adulthood.
My goal in this paper has been to render
plausible a number of inter-linked claims. I have tried to convince you of the
following, in particular. First, that childhood pretend play and adult creative
thinking and problem-solving share the same cognitive basis, namely the
capacity to generate an initial supposition, and to think and reason within its
scope. Second, that the evolutionary function of pretend play is best seen as
practice for adult creative thinking. And third, that what got selected for
between the first appearance of anatomically modern humans c.100,000 years ago
and the creative explosion of c.40,000 years ago was a disposition to engage
in pretend play in childhood. I have suggested that these claims, taken
together, constitute a hypothesis which is more plausible than any of the
competitors currently on the market. It is a hypothesis which is surely worthy
of further interdisciplinary investigation.
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to
Simon Baron-Cohen, Paul Harris, Stephen Laurence, Steven Mithen, and Shaun
Nichols for valuable advice and comments.
Department of
Philosophy
University of
Maryland
College Park
Maryland 20742
USA
Peter_Carruthers@umail.umd.edu
Amabile, T.
[1996]: Creativity in Context,
Boulder: Westview Press.
Bekoff, M. and
Byers, J. (eds.) [1998]: Animal Play, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bickerton, D.
[1995]: Language and Human Behavior,
Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Boden, M.
[1992]: The Creative Mind: myths and
mechanisms, New York: Basic Books.
Boden, M. (ed.) [1994]: Dimensions of Creativity, Boston: MIT Press.
Boyer, P.
[2000]: Evolution of a modern mind and the origins of culture: religious
concepts as a limiting case, in P. Carruthers and A. Chamberlain (eds.), 2000, Evolution and the Human Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 93-112.
Buss, D.
[1989]: Sex differences in human mate preferences: Evolutionary hypotheses
tested in 37 cultures, Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 12, pp. 1-49.
Carruthers, P.
[1996a]: Language, Thought and
Consciousness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P.
[1996b]: Autism as mind-blindness, in P. Carruthers and P.K. Smith (eds.), 1996, Theories of Theories of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 257-76.
Carruthers, P.
[1998a]: Thinking in language?: evolution and a modularist possibility, in P.
Carruthers and J. Boucher (eds.),
1998, Language and Thought,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 94-119.
Carruthers, P.
[1998b]: Conscious thinking: language or elimination?, Mind and Language, 13,
pp. 323-42.
Carruthers, P.
[2002]: The roots of scientific reasoning: infancy, modularity, and the art of
tracking, in P. Carruthers, S. Stich and M. Siegal (eds.), 2002, The Cognitive Basis of Science,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming.
Chomsky, N.
[1988]: Language and Problems of
Knowledge, Boston: MIT Press.
Chomsky, N.
[1995]: Language and nature, Mind, 104, pp. 1-61.
Dennett, D. [1991]: Consciousness Explained, London: Penguin
Press.
Dennett, D. [1995]: Darwins Dangerous Idea, London: Penguin
Press.
Diaz, R. and Berk,
L. (eds.) [1992]: Private Speech: From social interaction to
self-regulation, London: Laurence Erlbaum.
Finke, R. [1995]:
Creative realism, in S. Smith, T. Ward and R. Finke (eds.), 1995, The Creative
Cognition Approach, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 301-26.
Finke, R., Ward, T.
and Smith, S. [1992]: Creative Cognition,
Boston: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A. [1993]:
How we know our minds: the illusion of first-person knowledge of
intentionality, Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 16, pp. 1-14.
Gopnik, A. and
Melzoff, A. [1997]: Words, Thoughts and
Theories, Boston: MIT Press.
Harris, P. [2000]: The Work of the Imagination, Oxford:
Blackwell.
Hermer-Vazquez, L.,
Spelke, E. and Katsnelson, A. [1999]: Sources of flexibility in human
cognition: dual-task studies of space and language, Cognitive Psychology, 39,
pp. 3-36.
Hrdy, S. [1999]: Mother Nature: A history of mothers, infants
and natural selection, New York: Pantheon.
Jarrold, C.,
Carruthers, P., Smith, P. and Boucher, J. [1994a]: Pretend play: is it
meta-representational?, Mind and Language, 9, pp. 445-68.
Jarrold, C., Smith,
P., Boucher, J. and Harris, P. [1994b]: Comprehension of pretence in children
with autism, Journal of Autism and
Developmental Disorders, 24, pp.
154-67.
Jolly, A. [1999]: Lucys Legacy, Boston: Harvard
University Press.
Kosslyn, S. [1994]: Image and Brain, Boston: MIT Press.
Langley, P., Simon,
H., Bradshaw, G., and Zytkow, J. [1987]: Scientific
Discovery: Computational explorations of the creative process, Boston: MIT
Press.
Leslie, A. [1987]:
Pretence and representation, Psychological
Review, 94, pp. 412-26.
Leslie, A. [1991]:
The theory of mind impairment in autism, in A. Whiten (ed.), 1991, Natural Theories
of Mind, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 63-78.
Lewis, V. and
Boucher, J. [1998]: Spontaneous, instructed and elicited play in relatively
able autistic children, British Journal
of Educational Psychology, 6,
pp. 315-24.
Liebenberg, L. [1990]:
The Art of Tracking: The origin of
science, Cape Town: David Philip Publishers.
Locke, J. [1993]: The Childs Path to Spoken Language,
Boston: Harvard University Press.
Miller, G. [1997]:
Protean primates: The evolution of adaptive unpredictability in competition and
courtship, in A. Whiten and R. Byrne (eds.),
1997, Machiavellian Intelligence II,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 312-40.
Miller, G. [2000]: The Mating Mind: How sexual choice shaped
the evolution of human nature, London: Heinemann.
Mithen, S. [1996]: The Prehistory of the Mind, London:
Thames Hudson.
Mithen, S. [1998]: A
creative explosion? Theory of mind, language and the disembodied mind of the
Upper Paleolithic, in S. Mithen (ed.),
1998, Human Creativity in Archaeology and
Prehistory, London: Routledge, pp. 97-106.
Mithen, S. [2000]:
Mind, brain and material culture, in P. Carruthers and A. Chamberlain (eds.), 2000, Evolution and the Human Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 207-17.
Noble, W. and
Davidson, I. [1996]: Human Evolution,
Language and Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nichols, S. and
Stich, S. [2000]: A cognitive theory of pretence, Cognition, 74, pp.
115-47.
Perner, J. [1991]: Understanding the Representational Mind,
Boston: MIT Press.
Pinker, S. [1994]: The Language Instinct, London: Penguin
Press.
Power, C. [1999]:
Beauty magic: The origins of art, in R. Dunbar, C. Knight and C. Power (eds.), 1999, The Evolution of Culture, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
pp. 92-112.
Ryle, G. [1949]: The Concept of Mind, London: Hutchinson.
Shennan, S. [2000]:
Population, culture history and the dynamics of culture change, Current Anthropology, 41, 811-835.
Simpson, R. [1988]: Essentials of Symbolic Logic, London:
Routledge.
Smith, P. [1982]:
Does play matter? Functional and evolutionary aspects of animal and human play,
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 5, pp. 139-84.
Smith, S., Ward, T.,
and Finke, R. (eds.) [1995]: The Creative Cognition Approach, Boston:
MIT Press.
Sperber, D.
[1996]: Explaining Culture, Oxford:
Blackwell.
Sternberg, R. (ed.) [1988]: The Nature of Creativity: Contemporary psychological perspectives,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sternberg, R. (ed.) [1999]: Handbook of Creativity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stringer, C. and
Gamble, C. [1993]: In Search of the
Neanderthals: Solving the puzzle of human origins, London: Thames and
Hudson.
Ward, T., Smith, S.
and Finke, R. [1999]: Creative cognition, in R. Sternberg (ed.), 1999, Handbook of
Creativity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 189-212.
Watts, I. [1999]:
The origin of symbolic culture, in R. Dunbar, C. Knight and C. Power (eds.), 1999, The Evolution of Culture, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
pp. 113-48.
Wellman, H. [1990]: The Childs Theory of the Mind, Boston:
MIT Press.
Wittgenstein, L.
[1953]: Philosophical Investigations,
Oxford: Blackwell.
Wynn, T.
[2000]: Symmetry and the evolution of the modular linguistic mind, in P.
Carruthers and A. Chamberlain (eds.),
2000, Evolution and the Human Mind,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 113-39.
[1] This view of the late emergence of creative culture is by no means uncontroversial, and the absence of evidence of such culture from earlier eras may in fact be an artifact of poor preservation combined with dispersed populations (Shennan [2000]). Moreover, there is at least some evidence of the use of red ochre (presumably for body painting) from around 100,000 years ago (Power [1999]; Watts [1999]). In what follows, however, I shall assume that the late emergence of creative culture is a genuine phenomenon¾one which needs to be reckoned with by those proposing evolutionary explanations of human creativity.
[2] This then provides one of the main motives for those wishing to deny the reality of the gap between the first emergence of anatomically modern humans and the appearance of creativity some 60,000 years later. But, as I shall hope to show, there is at least one plausible evolutionary explanation of the change which may have taken place in the human genotype during this time.
[3] For example, the Cambridge Handbook of Creativity (Sternberg [1999]) contains no references to pretence and only two references to play within its 400+ densely-packed pages, despite the presence of a whole section of papers devoted to the evolutionary and developmental origins of human creativity.
[4] Leslie ([1987]) argues, in contrast, that what children need is the capacity to meta-represent their own representational states, hence de-coupling them from their normal connections with belief and action. See Jarrold et al. ([1994a]) and Nichols and Stich ([2000]) for critiques of this view.
[5] Mithen ([1998]) suggests that externalizations of cross-modular ideas (in the form of a carved lion/man figurine, say) may be necessary to make them memorable, hence stabilizing them for the first time in human cognition. But actually the psychological evidence is that such ideas are more memorable than those which are familiar and mundane. See Boyer [2000].
[6] Alternatively, Harris could combine his view with one or another version of the cultural accretions proposals criticized briefly above, suggesting that although the full capacity for creative thinking was present 100,000 years ago, it was not much employed at that time for accidental cultural reasons.
[7] Ritual burial is another matter. If pretence facilitates testimony about the not-here-and-now and religion involves beliefs about the not-here-and-now, then it is easy to see how such activities might in principle be dependent on pretend play.
[8] I like to model this on those natural-deduction systems in formal logic which employ the device of indented lines, or brackets down the side of the page, to keep track of the scope of any assumption (e.g. Simpson [1988]). Within that scope you may not assert anything categorically, except what has been imported from outside¾that is, which was already believed independently of the assumption. And only when the assumption is then dropped again by conditionalization can new assertions get made. For example, one assumes P, proves Q from it together with background assumptions, and can then, outside the scope of the assumption, assert If P then Q. Note, too, that such systems admit of multiple-embeddings of assumptions, just as new suppositions can get introduced into the scope of a pretence.
[9] This is a proposal which deserves to be worked-through thoroughly by both philosophers of mind and developmental psychologists, since in both disciplines there is a tendency to equate unpredictability with either noise or mere ignorance of initial conditions. But if Miller is right, then at least some forms of unpredictability will go much deeper into the human psyche.
[10] The author of the study was surprised by this result, having expected that male desire would be driven almost entirely by signs of fertility in women (i.e. by beauty). But he should not have been. In hunter-gatherer societies today female reproductive success is determined much more by resourcefulness than by fertility, and many women do not succeed in raising more than a single child to reproductive age (if they succeed in raising any), despite giving birth to many infants (Hrdy [1999]). The same was probably true throughout our evolutionary history. Small wonder, then, if men, too, should always have valued intelligence and problem-solving abilities in a potential long-term mate.
[11] Nichols and Stich ([2000]) actually label this element the script elaborator. This name is misleading, since it suggests that the supposer is only involved in elaborating sequences of pretence which are already in train; whereas they actually intend it to have the function of generating initial pretences as well (personal communication).
[12] Alternatively, we could suppose that the connections between imagination and the motivational system became strengthened with time, in a kind of mutually reinforcing loop. Perhaps the pleasures to be derived from pretence 100,000 years ago, and from imagining desired activities and experiences, were much less than they are now.