Return
to Animals Issue contents
3.
UTILITARIANISM AND ANIMAL SUFFERING
In this chapter I shall begin considering
what a utilitarian should say about the moral standing of animals. I shall
confine my attention to the question of the moral standing of animal experience
(particularly pleasure and pain), reserving to Chapter 4 discussion of
utilitarian approaches to the value of animal life.
Racism,
sexism, and speciesism
Peter Singer has been prominent in arguing
for the moral standing of animals and animal suffering, through such books as Animal Liberation[1]
and Practical Ethics. He does not, in
fact, explicitly premise his argument on any version of utilitarianism. For he
wants that argument to be acceptable to all, whatever their theoretical
stand-point. His strategy here is a good one. Any moral argument will be the
stronger for being able to survive translation between ethical theories, being
equally stateable in a variety of them. I shall show later that Singers
argument is only really acceptable from a utilitarian stand-point, however - in
particular, that it has no force against a contractualist.
Singers
argument starts from a principle of equal consideration of interests. This
holds that in any situation the interests of all those affected should be
considered equally, which may sound, on the face of it, like a utilitarian
principle. But in fact Singer is correct that, suitably interpreted, it should
be equally acceptable to contractualists. For contracting agents may reasonably
reject any rule that gives their interests no weight, or that treats those
interests as having less significance than those of other agents, as we shall
see in Chapter 5. It seems plain, in contrast, that no one could reasonably
reject a rule requiring us to treat everyones interests as of equal weight -
which is the principle of equal consideration of interests.
To
say that everyones interests should be given equal consideration is not to
say, of course, (for a contractualist at least) that everyones interests
should be met equally. Much will
depend upon the circumstances. If some of us have freely agreed to pay money
into a lottery, for example, then only those who have contributed may be
considered for a prize. This does not conflict with the principle of equal
consideration, since the others are not discriminated against - they were free
to take part if they wished. What would genuinely conflict with the principle
of equal consideration would be, for example, a policy of only considering for
prizes those with white skins, whether or not they have contributed to the
lottery.
Singers
explanation of the immorality of both racism and sexism is that these practices
violate the principle of equal consideration. For example, the policies of the
South African government through most of the decades of this century have
counted white interests as worth a lot, and the interests of blacks and
coloureds as being comparatively much less significant. Similarly, the policies
of many governments and individuals around the globe treat the interests of
women as worth less than those of men. These policies are wrong, and count as
violating the principle of equal consideration, because the characteristics of
skin colour and sex are morally irrelevant ones. While the fact of having
contributed money to a lottery is morally relevant when it comes to the
distribution of prizes, the fact of having white skin, or being male, is
plainly not. Indeed, there are hardly any important contexts in which these
latter features could be morally relevant. (Exceptions might be the distribution
of creams to prevent skin cancer in whites, and screening for testicular cancer
in men.)
Singers
main argument is then that speciesism, like racism and sexism, is wrong because
it discriminates on the basis of morally irrelevant characteristics. To give
lesser, or no, weight to the interests of animals violates the principle of
equal consideration because such a policy must be grounded in either the mere
differences of species between animals and ourselves, or in the differences of
appearance, or in the differences of intelligence. Yet none of these
characteristics is morally relevant, Singer argues. Let us discuss each of them
in turn.
It
seems plain that species membership is a morally irrelevant characteristic. Two
examples will suffice to make the point. First, suppose that the experiments
attempting to teach language to chimpanzees had been successful beyond their
originators wildest dreams. The apes in question gained a complete mastery of
English within a few years, were able to attend school and later university,
and made many close friendships with human beings. In these imaginary
circumstances it would plainly be absurd to claim that the apes lacked moral
standing, or had a moral importance that was lower than our own. At any rate,
to make these claims would plainly be morally objectionable in exactly the way
that similar claims made about members of different races are morally
objectionable. So species membership, in itself, cannot be a morally relevant
characteristic, serving to justify differential treatment of animals.
Consider
a second example to make the same point. It is well known that about ten per
cent of human couples are infertile. Then suppose it had been discovered that
the reason for this is that human beings in fact consist of two distinct
species, otherwise hardly distinguishable from one another, the members of
which cannot inter-breed. In these circumstances it would plainly be
objectionable for the members of the majority species to attempt to withhold
moral rights from the members of the minority, on the mere ground of difference
of species. This, too, would be obvious speciesism.
Now
consider two examples to make the point that differences of appearance between
humans and animals cannot serve as a moral ground for differential treatment of
the latter. First, consider human beings who have been victims of the drug
Thalidomide, taken by their mothers during early pregnancy. These people often
appear very different from normal humans, with perhaps no legs and just a few
fingers sprouting from a shoulder. But that is plainly no ground for treating
their interests as being lesser than our own. Second, suppose that there were
to be radiation victims following a nuclear accident who, while otherwise
normal human beings, were born covered with thick dark fur like monkeys. Again
these peoples difference in appearance from ourselves would plainly be no
ground for refusing to count them equally.
Finally,
consider two examples to make essentially the same point in connection with
differences of intelligence between animals and ourselves. Suppose that doctors
with a limited supply of kidney dialysis machines were to begin
intelligence-testing their kidney patients, only offering treatment to those
scoring above a certain level. Would there not be an immediate moral out-cry,
and rightly so? It is plainly morally repugnant to make life-or-death decisions
on the basis of intelligence. Similarly, suppose that a cosmetics company were
to begin testing their products in a home for severely retarded children, using
the same painful experiments currently employed on animals to ensure that their
products are safe. Again the out-cry would be immediate. The sufferings of
those children could not be ignored merely on the grounds that the children are
of lower intelligence than ourselves.
The
conclusion Singer draws from considerations of this sort is that it is morally
indefensible to exclude animals from the scope of the principle of equal
consideration of interests.[2]
Since the various characteristics that distinguish us from animals - that is,
species, appearance, and intelligence - are morally irrelevant, animal
interests should be counted equally with our own. Pain is pain, no matter who
feels it, and is just as morally significant. I shall shortly discuss one of
the presuppositions of Singers position - that animals do genuinely have
interests to be considered - and what the practical consequences of his
conclusion would be. But first I shall dig a little deeper into the notion of a
morally relevant characteristic.
The
relativity of relevance
My first thesis is a general one, that
relevance is always relative to a point of view. Imagine that Tania and Teresa
are watching a tennis game, and are asked whether or not it is relevant who
wins. Tania might reply that it is not, since she just likes to watch good
tennis. Teresa, on the other hand, might reply that it is, since she has a
substantial bet riding on the outcome of the game. What is relevant to the one
is irrelevant to the other, in virtue of the different perspectives that they
take towards the game - the different kinds of interest that they have in it.
So when it is claimed that species membership is a morally irrelevant
characteristic, we need to know the point of view being taken, in order to assess
the claim. That is, we need to know how the moral point of view is being
characterised. Once the matter is viewed in this light, it can be seen that
Singers argument is, in fact, only sound from the stand-point of a utilitarian
conception of morality.
Given
a contractualist conception of the moral point of view, intelligence - or at
least a certain kind and level of intelligence - is not morally irrelevant, as
we shall see in Chapter 5. On the contrary, for a contractualist it will turn
out to be a sufficient condition for a creature to have moral standing that it
should be a rational agent, and this is, broadly, a matter of its intelligence.
This explains the appeal of many of the examples used above, such as the
example of the English-speaking apes, and the examples of the Thalidomide and
radiation victims. For in each case it is plain that the individuals in
question are rational agents. To say that rational agency is morally relevant
under contractualism, however, is not to say that differences of intelligence
amongst rational agents must also have moral relevance. On the contrary, one
would expect rational contractors to outlaw discrimination on the basis of such
differences, of the kind involved in the example of the kidney dialysis
machines discussed above. For those who are of lower intelligence might surely
be reasonable in rejecting any rules that allow their interests to be
discounted, or counted for less.
It
is also the case that species membership, together with the similarities of
appearance and patterns of behaviour with which it is associated, is not
morally irrelevant under contractualism - at least if the arguments to be
presented in Chapters 5 and 7 are sound. There I shall argue that rational
contractors should extend direct moral rights to all members of the human
species, in order to avoid the dangers of a slippery slope and to preserve
social stability, and in order not to undermine our natural reactions of
sympathy for human suffering. Since these arguments do not support the extension
of direct moral rights to members of other species, it will turn out that
species membership is a morally relevant characteristic from the perspective of
contractualism.
From
this discussion it emerges that what really drives Singers argument is a
particular conception of the moral point of view, which identifies it with the
stand-point of an impartial benevolent observer, who is equally sympathetic to
the interests of all who are affected by a given action or situation.[3]
It also emerges that there is nothing
really driving Regans argument in The
Case for Animal Rights, which makes similar claims about the moral
irrelevance of species membership and intelligence.[4]
For as we saw in Chapter 1, Regan fails altogether to provide us with a
characterisation of the moral point of view, relying entirely, as he does, on
his - restricted - understanding of reflective equilibrium to establish his
views. Since we lack such a characterisation, we lack the means necessary to
assess his claims about moral relevance.
The
stand-point of the impartial benevolent observer is, you will recall from the
last chapter, the governing conception of utilitarianism, which regards moral
concerns as arising out of rationalised (impartial) sympathy. It is certainly
true that there can be no reason why an impartial observer should count animal
interests as of lower importance than our own. It is also true that rational
agency and species membership are both morally irrelevant, from the stand-point
of such an observer. The only relevant features are the capacity for pain and
pleasure, as well as the capacity for desire. Under utilitarianism the
boundaries of moral concern are co-extensive with the boundaries of sentience -
that is to say, with the capacity for experience. If an animal can suffer,
then, plainly, it may be said to have an interest in avoiding suffering. (Even
if you think that to have an interest in something implies, strictly speaking,
a desire for that thing, this point will still hold. For the very idea of pain
seems conceptually tied to the desire for its avoidance. If an animal can
suffer at all then it must have at least this one desire.) The principle of
equal consideration of interests will then require us to show equal respect for
the sufferings and frustrations of every sentient creature.
Singers
argument for extending the principle of equal consideration of interests to
animals is therefore less powerful than he would have liked. In particular,
that argument can have no force against someone who is already a convinced
contractualist. It is, indeed, an argument from the stand-point of
utilitarianism. What we are therefore investigating is what a utilitarian
should say on the subject of the moral standing of animal experience.
Do
animals have interests?
What a utilitarian (or, indeed, anyone else)
should say on this subject is partly dependent upon the facts. I have been
assuming, thus far, that animals do have experiences and at least some desires.
In which case, the only issue arising when we consider whether the principle of
equal consideration of interests should be applied to animals is the moral one.
But many have denied this. Many philosophers and psychologists have held that
animals are biological automata, lacking mental lives, and engaging in their characteristic
behaviours out of acquired habit or innately determined action sequences,
rather than because of anything resembling genuine cognition.
There
is no doubt that some animals are, in the relevant sense, automata, despite
their apparent sentience. When caterpillars hatch from their cocoons, for
example, they will climb to the tops of trees to eat the leaves at the tips of
the branches. But this apparently purposive behaviour is, in fact, a tropism - a mechanical feedback process
of a very simple sort. The caterpillars have two eyes, symmetrically positioned
on their heads. When the same amount of light enters each of the eyes the
caterpillars move straight ahead. But when more light enters one of the eyes
the legs on that side of the body move more slowly. The result is that the
caterpillars move towards the light. In experiments where the trees were
artificially lit from below, the caterpillars moved to the bottom of the trees,
where they remained even when starving. When a caterpillar was blinded in one
eye it would move endlessly in a circle, again to the point of starving.[5]
Caterpillars
will also wriggle vigourously when impaled on the end of a pin. It seems highly
likely that this, too, is a simple tropism. Although it might appear to a human
observer that the caterpillar is in pain, and is wriggling in an attempt to
avoid the source of the pain, in reality it is likely that the nerves sensitive
to the presence of the pin feed directly into the muscles responsible for the
subsequent movement, without any intervening cognition. Compare this case: you
are present at a medical examination of your daughter Patricia, and you observe
the doctor tap her on the knee with a hammer, upon which Patricia kicks out her
leg. An untutored observer might conclude that Patricia had tried to kick the
doctor because she felt pain at the blow. But you would know that it was, in
fact, a mere reflex. So, too, I suggest, in the case of the caterpillar.
It
seems unlikely that insects are genuinely sentient, in the sense of having
mental lives that would include sensations and desires. It is worth noting that
this is already to undermine one aspect of common-sense belief. Children who
pull the wings off flies, or the legs off ants, are told that it is cruel, and
to desist. In most cases their actions are presumably believed to be instances
of what Regan calls brutal cruelty (as opposed to sadistic cruelty)[6]
- that is, actions that display indifference to the suffering caused to others.
Yet these beliefs are false, if insects are not genuinely sentient. Once we
realise that insects feel no pain, the only remaining motive for discouraging
the children is that their activities are a sort of play-acting for real
cruelty. But in fact it would be equally effective to teach children to
distinguish between sentient and non-sentient creatures - supposing, at least,
that the distinction were known.
What,
then, are the boundaries of sentience? What sorts of creature are genuinely
capable of having pains and other experiences, and of having beliefs and
desires? I shall concentrate on the capacity for experience here, returning to
the question of animal beliefs and desires in Chapter 6. It seems safe to
assume that all mammals, at least, are genuinely sentient, given the variety
and flexibility of mammalian behaviours, and given the close similarities in
brain structure and function between even the lower mammals and ourselves.[7]
A variety of types of evidence also suggest that birds should be classed
together with mammals in respect of levels and degree of cognitive
organisation, and in contrast with lower vertebrates such as fish, amphibians,
and reptiles.[8] At any rate,
this is what I propose to assume - that all mammals and birds are genuinely
sentient, but that no insects are. For present purposes I shall remain agnostic
about the mental lives of lower vertebrates, since we have already done enough
to settle most of the cases relevant to the morally contentious practices of
hunting, farming, and animal experimentation. I shall assume that in all such
cases involving mammals and birds the animals can experience pain, and thus do
genuinely have interests to be considered.
Minds
and brains
Many of those who have maintained that human
beings are unique in the animal kingdom in possessing mental lives have done
so, in part, because they have denied that mental events and (some) brain
events are one and the same.[9]
These people have either held that humans have non-physical souls, which form
the true locus of their thoughts and feelings, or they have believed, at any
rate, that mental events are non-physical ones, partly caused by and partly
causing brain activity. Such people will then be unmoved by the manifest
similarities of structure and function between the brains of humans and higher
vertebrates.
It
is not strictly necessary that we should reject the doctrine of mental
immaterialism in order to maintain that higher vertebrates have genuine mental
lives. For we could hold that the considerable similarities in behaviour
between such animals and human beings would warrant ascribing non-material
mental events to both. But our case will be that much stronger if we can also
argue, as mental materialists, that the similarities between our brains suggest
corresponding similarities in cognition. It is, therefore, worth indicating
briefly why I hold that the thesis of mental immaterialism is false.
There
are two main arguments for maintaining that our mental lives must consist of
physical events in our brains. Both are premised on the common-sense belief
that mental events and brain events interact causally with one another. We
believe, for example, that retinal stimulation causes certain brain events that
cause in us visual sensations in turn, and that mental events such as decisions
cause bodily movements that have certain brain events as their immediate
causes.
The
first argument against mental immaterialism is that, if mental events are
non-physical, then we shall be required to recognize a whole new species of
causality, hitherto unknown to science. All the types of causal relationship
that science has given us reason to believe in - chemical, electrical,
mechanical, and so on - relate different classes of physical event. Indeed, it
can be said that the distinctive feature of scientific progress over the last
three centuries has been the assumption that there will be some sort of
physical mechanism underlying any causal relationship. Science really began to
make advances when people ceased to offer explanations in terms of causation by
spirits and other non-physical forces, and began to hunt for physical
mechanisms underlying the observed regularities in nature. The immense success
of science then gives us reason to extend this policy into the domain of the
mind until proved otherwise. But in fact, far from there being any proof of
mental immaterialism, the arguments for it are relatively weak.[10]
The
second main argument against mental immaterialism, and in favour of identifying
mental events with physical ones, is that enough is already known about the
brain for us to be confident that each brain event will have a sufficient
physical cause. We know that the human brain is made up of nerve cells, and
quite a lot is known about the causes of nerve cell activity. All of these
causes are physical ones, including chemical changes in the blood stream, as
well as the physical activation of connected cells. Given that this is so,
there is then no room for mental events (such as decisions) to cause brain
events (in this case the immediate causes in the brain of bodily movements)
unless mental events can be identified with the relevant brain events. If
decisions (and other mental events) can be causes of bodily movements, then
decisions must be brain events. For we know that bodily movements are caused by
brain events, each of which, in turn, has a sufficient physical cause.
It
is worth emphasising in conclusion of this section that mental materialism has
nothing whatever to do with materialism as a system of values. Nothing in what
has been said here commits us to the claim that the only things worth caring
about are wealth, power, and physical comfort. Nor need there be anything here
that is inconsistent with theological beliefs in life after death. For it is
possible to believe in resurrection of the body, as many Christians have, in
fact, done. Indeed, there might also be other forms of after-life available for
a mental materialist to believe in.[11]
Comparisons
of interest
I have been arguing that members of many
other species of animal, at least, should be counted as having interests,
because they are capable of experiencing pain. But what does the principle of
equal consideration of interests amount to, where the interests to be
considered may cross species boundaries? Are such comparisons of interest even
so much as possible? Similar worries to these can, in fact, be raised in
connection with comparisons of human interests. For it is possible to doubt
whether we can ever know the extent to which other people are really suffering,
or even whether they are suffering at all. But this is just the philosophical
problem of knowledge of other minds, raised for the particular case of
knowledge of other peoples experiences. Although this problem may be a
theoretically interesting one, few doubt that it must have a solution.[12]
That is to say, few are genuinely sceptical of our ability to have knowledge of
the mental states of other persons, based on our observations of their
behaviour.
If
this is so, then it would seem that essentially the same basis must exist for
knowledge of the mental states of animals. It is true that in connection with
the mental states of human beings we have one additional source of evidence,
namely those peoples descriptions of the qualities and intensities of their
experiences. But it is important to see that this is just one further piece of
behavioural evidence, having no special authority. For we still need to make
assumptions about the speakers sincerity and, more importantly, about what
they mean by the words that they use. These, in turn, can only be known by
means of an inference to the best explanation of the observed patterns in those
speakers behaviour.
There
are two different sorts of basis for our judgements of the extent of an
animals suffering. First, we can judge the intensity of that suffering from
direct observations of the animals behaviour - that is, from the degree of the
animals reaction (screaming or howling, for example), and how desperately it
tries to avoid the source of the pain. Second, we may judge the intensity of
the suffering by making reasonable hypotheses, on the basis of our observation
of other similar cases, about what the animal would be prepared to do to avoid
the suffering in question. Would it be prepared to endure a painful stimulus
like that in order to get food when it is extremely hungry, for example?
Physiological
differences between different animal species, of course, and between animals
and ourselves, rule out any simple comparisons of suffering. To use an example
of Singers, it is doubtful whether a hard slap to a horse would cause it as
much pain as would a similarly hard slap to a human baby. This is because the
horses skin is much thicker than that of the baby. But as Singer correctly
says, there must be some degree of
stimulus that would cause as much pain to the horse as does the slap to the
baby.[13]
And we would judge this by seeing how the horse reacts - how hard it tries to
get away, for example - and by seeing how much the horse would put up with to
get something that it really wants, such as water when it is dehydrated.
When
considering comparisons of suffering, Singer concedes that levels of
intelligence do in fact turn out to be important. In particular, the greater
intelligence of most humans gives vastly increased opportunities for suffering.
For example, imagine the varied sorts of suffering that would be involved in a
policy of random seizures of people off the streets, for use in painful
eye-tests of cosmetics. In the first place, of course, there would be the
immediate pain of the tests themselves, presumably roughly comparable to the
levels of pain experienced by laboratory rabbits. But then in addition, there
would be the fear beforehand, when people know that these seizures are taking
place, and when they know exactly what is going to happen to them once they are
seized. There would also be the memories remaining afterwards, perhaps with an
attendant destruction of the self-esteem of the person in question. For these
reasons Singer concedes that if these experiments have to be done at all, then
it is better that they should be performed on rabbits than on human beings,
since the suffering produced will be less. (He assumes, here, that most animals
will lack the sorts of higher mental processes of thought and feeling that give
rise to the kinds of additional sufferings mentioned above. I shall grant this
assumption for the moment, returning to discuss it in some detail in Chapter
6.) This concession of Singers is consistent with the principle of equal
consideration of interests, since it is only equal suffering that should be
considered equally.
Practical
consequences
As we have seen, Singer allows that
cross-species comparisons of interests are very difficult to conduct with any
degree of accuracy, and that the greater intelligence of most humans vastly
increases their capacity for suffering. But he also claims that we only have to
be able to make the very roughest of comparisons in order to have an enormous
impact on current practices in the treatment of animals. Let us consider in
turn the four main categories of hunting, factory farming, cosmetic testing,
and medical testing.
People
who go hunting often consume the meat of the animals that they kill, and they
often wear or sell their skins. But it is arguable that these benefits should
not enter into the moral equation at all, since animal pain is not really
necessary to provide them. In our modern world meat and furs can be obtained by
normal farming, which need involve no suffering for the animals. Such animals
can in principle be kept in pleasant conditions throughout their lives before
being slaughtered painlessly and unexpectedly. (Recall that the question of the
moral standing of animal lives is
being deferred to Chapter 4.) So the only relevant advantages to humans from
hunting are the pleasures of the hunt itself - tracking, stalking, or chasing
an animal, and then trying to kill it. It is in the nature of this activity
that it cannot be carried out without frequently causing pain to the animals
involved.
Now
although the pleasures of hunting, for some people, may be considerable, they
are surely trivial by comparison with the painful death frequently endured by
the animal. If the pain and terror caused by a fatal wound in a deer or rabbit
is even roughly comparable to what a human would feel in similar circumstances,
then it is obvious that they greatly outweigh any pleasure felt by the hunter.
For consider: would even the most dedicated of hunters pursue their sport, if
they themselves had to endure suffering comparable to that of each animal they
failed to kill cleanly? It seems plain that they would not. In which case,
applying the principle of equal consideration of interests here will show
hunting to be wrong.
Now
consider the practice of factory farming. Here again the suffering caused to
the animals, through being kept in extremely cramped and unnatural conditions,
is considerable. Yet the only gain to humans is that we should enjoy cheaper
(and in some cases, perhaps, tastier) meat. So for each animal that suffers, the
proportion of its suffering that is caused by factory farming, throughout the
course of its life, has to be set against the marginal pleasures of the dozens
of humans who eventually have a share in consuming its flesh. If that animal
had not been factory farmed, then the only loss to those people is that they
would each have had rather less money to spend on other things.
In
this case, too, the application of the principle of equal consideration of
interests seems easy. The gains to human beings - even when totalled up -
appear trivial when compared with the extensive suffering of the animals. In
which case factory farming will be wrong from the stand-point of a utilitarian.
It is important to note, however, that this does not yet justify moral
vegetarianism (as opposed, for example, to vegetarianism adopted for reasons of
health). For some utilitarians (Singer included) hold the view that while it is
wrong to cause animals suffering, it is permissible to kill them painlessly. So
farming methods where the animals are kept in enjoyable conditions throughout
their lives before being painlessly killed for their meat, may turn out to be
morally unobjectionable. What utilitarians should say about this will depend on
their views on killing in general, and on the value of animal life in
particular, which we shall discuss in the next chapter.
The
case against cosmetics testing on animals seems equally clear-cut. For the
tests are such that the animals in question suffer very severe pain, whereas
the gains to humans of being able to use a new cosmetic are marginal. Now it
might be replied that in an age of mass-production, even fairly minor pleasures
brought to millions of people might easily outweigh the intense sufferings of a
few hundred animals. But the pleasures in question are very marginal indeed.
For there are already a wide range of cosmetics products in existence. The only
cost of banning testing now, would be the loss of the pleasure that some people
feel on being able to try something completely new.
There
is, however, a point about those who are employed in the cosmetics industry,
many of whom might lose their jobs if testing of new products were banned.
(This issue does not arise in connection with factory farming, since
traditional farming methods are more, rather than less, labour-intensive.) Here
the issue is in danger of merging into complex questions of economics and
social policy. But as a corrective to it, try to take seriously the application
of the principle of equal consideration of interests to animals. For if it were
young children rather than animals who were involved, for example, then how
many people could seriously place their possession of a job higher than the
option of avoiding the suffering that their jobs produce?
Finally,
consider the use of animals in painful scientific experiments, particularly
those connected with the development and testing of new medicines. This is in
many ways the most difficult case, because of the very considerable gains that
may result from such experiments, through reducing or avoiding the incidence of
painful illnesses in both humans and animals. Might not these benefits outweigh
the sufferings of the animals used in the tests? In some cases, surely, they
might. But in order to justify any particular series of experiments, we would
need to have an assurance that the probability of such benefits accruing is
quite high. A mere chance of great benefit will not be enough, when set against
the certainty of the suffering caused to the animals involved. In any case,
what Singer suggests here as a useful rule of thumb, is that such tests are
morally acceptable only if it would be equally acceptable to perform them on
mentally retarded orphan humans.[14]
(They should be orphans to rule out the question of vicarious suffering caused
to parents and relatives.) If this would not be acceptable (as presumably it
would not, for most people), then from a utilitarian stand-point it can only be
unacceptable speciesism to allow the tests in question to be conducted on
animals of similar intelligence.
Is
reflective equilibrium possible?
Utilitarianism is clearly committed to making
substantial revisions in the common-sense moral beliefs held by most people. It
entails (when taken together with reasonable assumptions about the reality of
animal experience) that hunting, factory farming, cosmetics testing, and many
of the uses of animals in medical experiments are all seriously wrong, and
should be stopped. For from the stand-point of the governing conception of
utilitarianism - that of an impartial benevolent observer - there can be no
reason why the interests of animals should be discounted or outweighed where
they conflict with those of human beings. If these consequences are to be
acceptable under reflective equilibrium, then we need somehow to explain away
the almost universal human belief in their contraries - for example, the belief
that the interests of an animal count for practically nothing when set against
the suffering of a human being.
Utilitarians
have a reply to this difficulty, explaining how it is that most people have
had, until now, false beliefs about the extent of the moral significance of
animals. For the impartial perspective is by no means an easy one to attain.
Indeed, moral progress can be characterised, for a utilitarian, as a constant
struggle against our own natural partiality. We are all naturally partial to
those who are closest to us, linked to us by ties of blood or affection. Hence
the most primitive form of morality is the morality of the clan, withholding
moral standing from all outsiders. But reason can gradually modify this
partiality, forcing us to recognize that there is no rational basis for
counting the interests of those close to us above the interests of other
people. In addition, a utilitarian can point out that there have been long
periods of human history when an argument for equal consideration of the
interests of slaves and slave owners would have struck most people as equally
counter-intuitive. So our initial intuitive reaction to the claim that the
interests of animals should be counted equally with our own might be claimed to
be no more than a product of our natural (but unreasonable) partiality towards
members of our own species.
This
reply might have been considered adequate, if there had been no other
theoretical alternatives available. That is, if we had been faced with a choice
between having no coherent theory of morality at all, and one which entailed
equal moral standing for animals, it might - perhaps - have been more
reasonable to opt for the latter. For similar reasons, the envisaged reply
might also have been acceptable if utilitarianism had enjoyed huge theoretical
advantages over all alternative moral theories. But these are not in fact the
choices before us. For we do have an alternative theory, namely contractualism.
This is equally, if not more, theoretically defensible, and can explain the
duties towards animals postulated by common-sense morality without granting
moral standing to animals, as we shall see in Chapter 7. Given this situation,
I propose that the way to achieve reflective equilibrium is to reject
utilitarianism altogether, and embrace contractualism instead.
It
is worth emphasising that the prohibitions against hunting, factory farming,
and laboratory testing on animals are by no means the most counter-intuitive
consequences of the utilitarian approach to this issue. Indeed, many ordinary
people may hardly find them counter-intuitive at all. Rather, the hardest thing
to accept is that the suffering of an animal should have equal moral standing with the (equally severe) suffering of a human
being. An imaginary example will make the point vivid. Suppose that Saul is a
very powerful and evil sadist. You have discovered that in the dungeons of his
castle he keeps a number of creatures, including a human being, in conditions
of perpetual torture. Now imagine yourself on a rescue mission to his castle.
You have somehow discovered a way in, that can only be used once, and you know
that you will only have time to release just one of those who are undergoing
torture, before the alarm bells start to ring and you are captured yourself.
What
should you do? Utilitarianism, being committed to the extension of the
principle of equal consideration of interests to animals, entails that, other
things being equal, there is nothing to choose - morally speaking, you are free
to release any one of the imprisoned creatures at random. Indeed, if one of
those creatures were to have a natural life-expectancy greater than that of the
human - perhaps an elephant or giant turtle - then a utilitarian might have to
claim that you are morally obliged to rescue the animal. These consequences are
hugely counter-intuitive. I think most of us would feel that you are under a
strong moral obligation to liberate the human being, and that you would,
normally, do something very wrong indeed if you chose to save a dog, or an
elephant, or a monkey instead.
It
is important not to become distracted by irrelevancies at this point. It should
be supposed, for example, that you have evidence that is as good as it can be
that the degree of suffering of the imprisoned human is no greater than that of
the animals. (You may perhaps have had the opportunity to study in detail
videotapes of the torture in progress.) Moreover, it should be supposed that
you know that the torture of each creature will continue until its natural
death, and is of such a severity that it leaves no space in consciousness for
any further thought. This is to side-step the point about the additional
suffering that the human may later undergo, by re-living the torture in memory,
and also the point that the human may suffer additionally through hopelessness
and fear of suffering further. Suppose, too, that the human in question is
quite old, with a life expectancy no greater than any of the dogs, cats, or
monkeys involved. So there is nothing to be gained in the way of additional
future happiness by saving the human being. Despite all this, the intuition
remains that it would be unforgivable to do anything other than rescue the
human being. My view is that this belief is so deeply and firmly held, by most
of us, that any moral theory that requires its rejection ought, in turn, to be
rejected under reflective equilibrium.
In
reply, it may be said that many people have in fact found it quite easy to lose
this intuition, and have embraced with enthusiasm the thesis of the equal moral
standing of animal suffering, but without especially adopting a utilitarian
stand-point. This is true. But so too, and in the same sense, have people
managed to lose their belief in the physical world. In both cases the basic
form of the argument is sceptical.
Those who have lost their belief in physical reality have done so because they
doubted whether there is anything that justifies belief in a world of physical
objects, given that it is possible for our experiences to be a gigantic
hallucination, or to be caused by an evil demon working directly on our minds.
Similarly, many of those who have lost their belief in the differential moral
standing of human and animal suffering have done so because they doubted
whether there is anything that justifies belief in the difference. But, in
common with many other philosophers, I believe that scepticism about physical
reality is answerable.[15]
And it will be the task of Chapters 5 and 7 to answer scepticism about the
unequal moral standing of animal suffering. In both cases the sceptical
argument is initially attractive (not to say seductive), hard to answer, but
ultimately unsound.
Most
utilitarians will probably concede that they are in conflict with a key aspect
of common-sense moral belief on the issue of animal suffering. But, they may
claim, the forces of progress are on their side, in such a way that future
generations will judge them, in retrospect, to have been correct. Our current
attitudes towards animals, on this analysis, are similar to eighteenth century
attitudes towards slavery and members of inferior races. Indeed, many
utilitarians are fond of pointing out that there have been numerous periods of
human history in which the extension of the principle of equal consideration of
interests to members of other races would have seemed equally counter-intuitive
to most ordinary people. Yet we now judge that those people were wrong, and
that the minority who protested against such practices as slavery were right.
In
fact, however, the two cases are importantly different. For there has never
really been a theoretically respectable moral theory that could justify a
system of slavery, at least in any of the forms that have actually been
practiced. (Recall from Chapter 2 that utilitarianism itself may imply that in
certain - hypothetical - circumstances an institution of slavery would be
justified.) In particular, contractualism, too, entails that slavery was, and
is, seriously wrong. Indeed, what more obvious breach could there be of the
central contractualist principle of respect for autonomy? All that really
sustained common-sense beliefs about the permissibility of slavery were false -
and probably self-deceived, certainly self-interested - beliefs about the
inferior cognitive powers of members of other races. Once these beliefs were
overturned, justifications for slavery collapsed without the need for any
further theoretical argument.
There
is, in contrast, a genuine theoretical dispute about the moral standing of
animals. For, as we shall see in Chapters 5 and 7, contractualism entails that
such standing should be withheld from animals, while it at the same time
accommodates almost all the elements of common-sense moral belief. At no point
does this theoretical case rely upon false beliefs about the cognitive powers
of animals. Indeed, it is just as much a part of common-sense that animals have
mental lives in many respects like our own, as it is that their sufferings and
interests cannot be counted equally with ours. So in the case of animals, in
contrast with the case of opposition to slavery in the past, utilitarianism is
urging a substantial moral change upon us that is insufficiently motivated.
Since it will turn out that there is, in fact, a moral theory that would
preserve the status quo while being
equally (at least) as theoretically attractive as utilitarianism, it must be
unreasonable for us to accept such a change.
Higher
and lower pleasures
I can think of just one way in which a
utilitarian might hope to avoid the consequence that there is no obligation, in
an example like that of Saul, the sadist, to opt for the prevention of human
suffering above the prevention of animal suffering. This is by appealing to a
distinction between higher and lower pleasures, that is in any case sometimes
defended by utilitarians. It is sometimes said that there are pleasures, such
as those of listening to a Schubert piano sonata, that are higher than others,
such as the pleasures of eating or of masturbation.[16]
These (broadly intellectual) pleasures are said by some utilitarians to be
intrinsically more valuable, counting for more in any calculation of overall
utility. This distinction between higher and lower pleasures will loom large in
the chapter that follows, but it is worth briefly considering, now, how it
might be deployed at this point in the argument.
We
might wonder, on the face of it, how the distinction between different orders
of pleasure could apply to the example of Saul, the sadist, at all. For in that
example no pleasure is in question, only physical pain. And this we are
presuming to be the same in both quality and intensity in both human and
animal. But this is to forget that one of the characteristic effects of pain,
particularly if it is intense, is to interfere with other enjoyments,
especially those that are cognitive in nature. Those who doubt this should try
making love while suffering from a migraine, or listening to a Schubert sonata
with one. It may then be said that while the pain undergone by a human being is
intrinsically no more morally significant than the suffering of an animal, the
human case is distinctive in that the pain also prevents enjoyment of pleasures
that are higher. So the suggestion is that we may explain our intuition in the
example of Saul, the sadist, as follows. The human being definitely ought to be
the one to be rescued, because if that human were not undergoing torture, then
at least some of their time would be occupied with pleasures that are higher
than those that would occupy the time of a dog or a monkey if they were not being tortured.
As
I say, the distinction between higher and lower pleasures will be considered in
the next chapter, where I shall argue that it is of doubtful coherence. But it
does not, in any case, really get a utilitarian out of the present difficulty,
as can easily be seen. For suppose you know that the human who is undergoing
torture is a convinced hedonist, of a sort who would in fact devote their
entire time to the pursuit of lower pleasures if rescued. Or, if it is thought
that experience of torture may be sufficient to cure anyone of hedonism,
suppose that the human being in question is mentally retarded, so that they are
constitutionally incapable of enjoying any but the lower pleasures. These
possibilities make not the slightest difference to my intuition that it would
be wrong to do anything other than rescue the human being. In which case, it
cannot be the characteristic human capacity for intellectual pleasures that
underlies the intuition.
Quality-of-character-utilitarians can perhaps
reply to this argument. They can claim that our habit of taking human suffering
more seriously than the comparable suffering of an animal has been formed in
circumstances in which human suffering normally does (but animal suffering does
not) interfere with the pursuit of higher pleasures. Then the intuition that I
take so seriously in the case of Saul, the sadist - that it would be wrong to
save the dog before the human being - may merely reflect this habitual way of
thinking, which itself has a utilitarian justification.
There
are two points to be made about this reply. The first is that it is a double
edged weapon. For it is plain that most ordinary people do not seriously rate
animal suffering at all, in comparison to the sufferings of human beings. A
quality-of-character-utilitarian might then be expected to urge, as a
corrective to this, that we should try to develop in ourselves a disposition to
take animal sufferings more seriously
than the sufferings of humans. This is on the sound Aristotelian principle,
that if you are trying to mold a quality of character that is difficult for us
to attain, you should aim, initially at least, to exaggerate it - by
overshooting the mark, you may hit the target.[17]
So the quality of character that is manifested in our judgement that it would
be wrong to rescue the dog first is arguably lacking in utilitarian
justification in any case, even supposing that the distinction between higher
and lower pleasures could be made out. For we ought, on utilitarian grounds, to
be trying to become the sort of people who take animal suffering more seriously
than we do.
The
second point that should be made against the above reply is to note that
reflective equilibrium, in its widest sense, must essentially involve
comparison between moral theories, as
well as mutual adjustment of theoretical detail and ordinary belief within a given theoretical approach. For
I take it that our common-sense intuition in the case of Saul, the sadist, is
not simply that it would be wrong to rescue an animal before the human (which
might perhaps be explained by appeal to the distinction between higher and
lower pleasures), but that it is wrong to weight the suffering of an animal
equally with the equal suffering of a human being. So the plausibility of
suggesting that our intuition in this case should be rejected needs to be
contrasted with the relevant theoretical alternatives. As we shall see in
Chapter 7, contractualism can explain all the main elements of common-sense
moral belief here without having to give up this intuition. It should
therefore, other things being equal, be preferred - especially given the
strength of our feeling on the issue.
Summary
There is an argument for saying that speciesism is just as morally objectionable as racism or sexism. This argument would, if accepted, have important implications for our practices that cause suffering to animals, such as hunting and factory farming, since there are good reasons for believing that higher vertebrates, at least, have interests. But in fact the argument presupposes that the moral stand-point may be equated with that of an impartial sympathetic observer, which is the governing conception of utilitarianism. Moreover, the fact that utilitarianism has such a consequence renders it reflectively unstable, since the conclusion is at odds with apparently fundamental features of our moral thought. Even an appeal to the distinction between higher and lower pleasures cannot really help. The utilitarian approach to animal suffering is therefore inadequate, and should be rejected.
[1] Jonathan Cape, 1975; 2nd edition, 1990.
[2] See Practical Ethics, ch. 3.
[3] For Singer's commitment to this characterisation of the moral point of view, see Practical Ethics, ch. 1.
[4] See The Case for Animal Rights, ch. 5 & p. 261.
[5] See H. Rachlin, Behaviour and Learning (Freeman, 1976), pp. 125-6.
[6] See The Case for Animal Rights, p. 197.
[7] See Stephen Walker, Animal Thought (Routledge, 1983), chs. 4 & 5.
[8] See Walker, Animal Thought, ch. 6.
[9] For a recent example, see Peter Harrison Do Animals Feel Pain?' Philosophy 66 (1991).
[10] See my Introducing Persons (Routledge, 1986), chs. 2-3 & 5, and also Peter Smith and O. R. Jones, The Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1986), part one.
[11] See my Introducing Persons, ch. 7.
[12] For example, see my Introducing Persons, chs. 1 & 4-6.
[13] See Practical Ethics, p. 52.
[14] See Practical Ethics, p. 59.
[15] See my Human Knowledge and Human Nature, chs. 11-12.
[16] Most of those who employ the higher/lower distinction would put the pleasures of sex in general on the lower' side of the divide. This is a definite mistake. Normal human sex has an irreducibly intellectual component. For I do not just enjoy my own sensations (as I do when masturbating) - I am also aware that my partner is enjoying hers, and that she is similarly aware of, and takes further pleasure in, the fact that I am enjoying mine; and I enjoy that too. In fact there is nothing animal about human sex; it is a matter of mutual enjoyment in the fullest sense. In this much I follow Thomas Nagel, Sexual Perversion', in his Mortal Questions (Cambridge University Press, 1979).
[17] See Aristotle, Ethics (c.330 BC), bk. 2, final sect.