Return
to Animals Issue contents
4.
UTILITARIANISM AND THE HARM OF KILLING
In this chapter I shall conclude my
discussion of the implications of utilitarianism for the question of the moral
standing of animals, by considering what a utilitarian should say about the
value of animal life.
Dying,
killing, and harming
I argued in Chapter 3 that utilitarians are
committed to extending the principle of equal consideration of interests to
animals, and that this would then imply that it is morally wrong to cause an
animal to suffer, except in unusual circumstances. Some utilitarians, including
Singer, have thought that the principle of equal consideration applies to
animals very differently when it comes to the question of killing them. Some
have argued, indeed, that there is no moral objection to killing an animal,
provided that the death is unexpected and painless. We then get a moral
position that does not entail moral vegetarianism, while it would rule out
hunting and factory farming. Alternatively, some have argued that, while there
are moral objections to killing animals, the value of animal life is much lower
than that of persons. So although it is wrong to kill an animal for no reason,
much less reason is required than is necessary to justify the killing of a
person. The main arguments for these views will be considered in later
sections. I shall begin by drawing some preliminary distinctions.
It
is important to keep three different questions, that are often run together,
separate from one another. The first is whether death is harmful to the one who
dies, and if so, in what respect it is harmful. There is an ancient puzzle
about this. For there is a problem, both about the subject who is harmed by
death, and about the time at which the harm occurs. Before a person dies, there
is presumably no harm, since death has not yet occurred. But as soon as the
moment of death arrives, there is no longer anyone in existence to be harmed.
(Since this book is written from a secular perspective, I shall assume
throughout that death is the end of existence, for both persons and animals.[1])
Many have therefore concluded that death is not, in itself, a harm at all, and
that we suffer no evil by dying.
The
second question is whether we have reason to be afraid of death. This is easily
confused with the first, but is really quite distinct from it. Many who hold
that death is not an evil believe that it follows from this that it is
irrational to fear death. They argue that those who are afraid of death are
mistakenly picturing the time after their death as a sort of positive, but
empty, state - the state of existing in utter blankness. Whereas the reality is
that those who are dead no longer exist at all. It is then argued that fear of
death only arises because we mistakenly confuse the end of consciousness with an empty
consciousness. But this is not so. Even if death is not a harm, it may still be
rational to fear it. For our reasons for wanting to go on living are not that
we wish to avoid the harm of death, but rather that continued life is a
presupposition of most of our projects and desires. That I should not die
first, is a necessary condition for satisfying almost any desire. (Exceptions
would be desires for martyrdom and posthumous fame.) Therefore, in so far as I
have desires for the future that require my continued existence, I shall also
have reason to fear death. For in general, we have reason to fear anything that
may prevent our desires from being satisfied.
The
third question, that is closely related to, but distinct from, the other two,
is why it is directly wrong to kill (ignoring side-effects, such as grief
caused to loved ones and so on). If death is a harm, then this will receive an
answer within utilitarianism - it is because killing causes harm. But even if
death is not a harm, it may still be directly wrong to kill, at least from a
contractualist perspective. This will be because killing infringes the agents
autonomy - indeed, it is the ultimate infringement of autonomy. Since agents
will generally have projects and desires that require their continued
existence, they will not wish to be killed. In which case, killing them will
infringe their right to pursue their projects without interference. If rational
agents have reason to fear death, then it is obvious that rational contractors
should agree not to kill one another, except in self-defence.
Our
main question in this chapter, is whether the direct utilitarian objections to
the killing of persons (ignoring side-effects) extend also to the killing of
animals. I shall argue that they do. But first we must consider whether death
is a harm, and if so in what respect.
The
harm of death
The position of those who believe that death
is not a harm may be summed up in the old adage What you dont know cant hurt
you. On this view, since those who have died are no longer in existence to
feel any deprivation, no harm has resulted to them from their deaths. The old
adage is not strictly true, however. Something can harm me if it prevents me
from enjoying things that I would otherwise have enjoyed, even if I never know
and never feel the lack. Suppose that a rich uncle of whom I have never heard
dies, leaving me millions in his will. But I never learn that this has
happened, because a clever lawyer manages to defraud me of my inheritance. Here
I may rightly be said to have been harmed by the lawyers action, even though I
never feel the lack of the money. For there are many satisfactions that I would
have enjoyed had the lawyer not interfered. Preventing someones satisfaction
is just as much a way of harming them as causing them dissatisfaction.
In
the light of this, it is obvious that there is one respect in which death is,
normally, a harm to the one who dies. (Of course there are rare circumstances
in which life is so awful that continued existence is no blessing - in which
the person would be, as we say, better off dead. Recall the example of Anthony,
the author, from Chapter 1.) For it will generally be true that if the
individual had not died, then they would have continued to enjoy a satisfying
existence. Death is then a harm, not because it causes us positive deprivation
- not because it causes us felt dissatisfaction - but because it prevents us
from enjoying satisfactions that we would otherwise have had. Death is a harm,
not because of what it is, but for what it does - it cuts off future worthwhile
existence.
Some
have argued that there is quite another sense in which death is a harm to the
one who dies, namely, that it causes many of that persons desires to be objectively dissatisfied.[2]
But this will take some explaining. We first of all need to distinguish between
objective and subjective satisfactions of desire. A desire is objectively
satisfied if the event desired does in fact take place, whether the person
knows of it or not. A desire is subjectively satisfied, in contrast, if the
person comes to believe that the event desired has taken place, whether it
really has or not. Suppose that I want the Washington Redskins to win the
Superbowl, for example. Then imagine two scenarios. In the first, the Redskins
really do win, but, as a result of some sort of misinformation, I come to
believe that they have not. Then my desire is objectively, but not
subjectively, satisfied. In the second scenario, the Redskins fail to win, but
I somehow come to believe that they have. Then my desire has been subjectively,
but not objectively, satisfied.
It
might be claimed, against this distinction, that every desire aims at its own
subjective satisfaction - in which case it is impossible for a desire to be
objectively satisfied without being subjectively satisfied. So it might be said
that when I want the Redskins to win the Superbowl, what I really want is the
felt satisfaction of learning that they win. But this is plainly false, for two
reasons. First, when I am pleased that the Redskins have won, I am pleased because I have got what I wanted. The
pleasure is a result of my desire being satisfied, not what the desire was
really a desire for. Felt satisfaction is a normal concomitant of the knowledge
that a desire has been objectively satisfied, rather than being what every
desire really aims at. The truth is certainly not that I wanted the Redskins to
win because I guessed that their winning would please me! Second, many of our
desires in any case aim at things that we know we shall never see happen. For
example, many of us have desires for things about which we are quite
clear-headed that they will only be realised after our deaths, such as the
desire that our grand-children should live to a happy old age. Plainly we are
not in this case wanting to see our
grand-children live to a happy old age (though we may have that - impossible -
desire as well).
With
the distinction between objective and subjective satisfactions of desire in
place, Nagels thesis can now be stated. It is that both objective and
subjective frustrations of desire are a species of harm. Then death is a harm
to the one who dies because all of that persons desires for the future that
involve their own continued existence are thereby objectively frustrated. For
example, if I want to be rich and want to be famous, but die before I can
become either, then those desires will have been objectively frustrated. Of
course I will not feel any
dissatisfaction, since I shall no longer exist. But it will be true that the
things I wanted did not in fact take place, because death prevented them from
happening. In which case death has harmed me, if objective frustrations of
desire count as harms.
Is
Nagel correct to claim, however, that objectively frustrated desires are a
species of harm? The question is an important one for us, on the assumption
that animals have many fewer, if any, desires for the future (an assumption we
shall examine in Chapter 6). For then death will be much less of a harm for
them, if a large part of the harm of death for humans consists in the objective
frustration of our forward-looking, long-term, desires.
In
order to test Nagels thesis, let us consider an example in some detail.
Suppose that Kurt is married to Philippa, and wants very much that Philippa
should be faithful to him. Philippa, however, has other ideas, and carries on a
love affair with another man without Kurt discovering. Suppose that nothing in
Philippas relationship with Kurt ever suffers as a result - so far as Kurt is concerned,
things are just as they would have been if Philippa had in fact been faithful
to him throughout. Is Kurt harmed by Philippas infidelity, merely because his
desire that she should be faithful to him is objectively frustrated, and
despite the fact it is subjectively satisfied? I do not believe that he is.
I
admit to feeling a certain pull in the contrary direction. But I think that
this can be explained. For we can distinguish at least two senses in which
everyone, including utilitarians, might agree that what Philippa does is bad
(quite apart from any question of breach of contract), but which neither of
them amount to any misfortune for Kurt. First, we might allow that what
Philippa does is bad, in the sense
that she has taken a real risk of harming Kurt. For no matter how careful she
may be, there is always a chance that Kurt will find out. Second, there is a
sense in which it is bad for someone to be exposed to risk. Something bad has
surely happened to an atomic power worker who becomes contaminated by
radiation, for example, because of the risk that this will cause serious
disease to develop in later life. But consider the situation after the fact. If
the power worker lives to a ripe old age and dies of a heart attack, then no
harm was in fact done by the exposure to radiation. Similarly, imagine yourself
reviewing Kurts life shortly after his eventual death. He remained happily
married to Philippa throughout, and never in fact discovered her infidelity.
Then surely he was not harmed either. Although something he wanted not to
happen did in fact happen, he was not harmed by it. This is because he never
knew of it, and because (in the light of our earlier discussion of the
fraudulent lawyer), it did not prevent him from enjoying satisfactions that he
would otherwise have enjoyed.
For
some people, the intuition that Kurt is harmed by Philippas action may survive
the points made above. As someone might put it, The harm done to Kurt is that
his desire was for the real thing and what he got was fraudulent.[3]
But I think that this intuition derives from a wholly different perspective on
ethics (namely, contractualism), and that there is no way in which it can be
available to a utilitarian. I shall explain this briefly now, returning to the
point, from a slightly different angle, in a later section.
It
is true, of course, that what people generally want is the real thing, not a plausible substitute. (When Kurt
wants Philippa to be faithful to him he wants just that - that she should be
faithful - not that he should continue to believe that she has been faithful.)
For this reason rational contractors cannot agree to principles that would
prohibit them from subjectively frustrating the desires of others in certain
circumstances, but allowing them objectively to frustrate those desires, even
provided that there is no danger that the person in question should find out.
For example, it might plausibly be held that marriage (or at least a certain
kind of marriage) gives rise to an obligation to take the important desires and
projects of our partners seriously, trying not to frustrate those desires if we
can. Now, the important point is that this obligation, viewed from a
contractualist perspective, has to be understood as dealing with objective satisfactions of desire. Since
what we aim at is the real thing, it would be intolerable that we should agree
to principles that would give equal credit to plausible substitutes. (This
follows, I think, from the contractualist commitment to the ideal of publicity in moral principles.) So it
may be that Philippa fails in her obligations to Kurt, even supposing that
there is no real danger of him finding out.
I
thus maintain that the intuition that Kurt has been harmed may derive, in the
end, from the fact that wrong has been done him, understood from a
contractualist perspective. So this is not a harm that a utilitarian can
recognize. To see this clearly, we need an example where the putative harm is
caused accidentally (so there is no question of wrong-doing), and where it is
clear that there is no danger that objective dissatisfaction should ever become
subjective (so there is no harm in the sense of risk, either). To this end, let
me introduce the example of Astrid, the astronaut, variants of which will recur
at various points through the remainder of this book.
Suppose
that Astrid is a very rich woman, who has become tired of life on Earth with
its squalor and constant violence. Accordingly, she buys herself a
space-rocket, and takes off on a trajectory that is set irreversibly to carry
her out of our solar system, and forever out of contact with her fellow humans.
She does not even carry with her a radio with which she can be contacted. Now
suppose that before leaving Earth she had erected a statue in memory of her beloved
late husband, and one of her most cherished desires is that the statue should
outlast her. But within months of her departure the statue is struck by
lightning and destroyed. Is Astrid harmed? It seems to me plain that she is
not, since she can never know. Yet her desire has been objectively frustrated.
This confirms my suggestion that what really underpins the intuition that harm
has been done, in cases such as Kurts, is that wrong has been done, involving either a risk of harm, or an
infringement of principles that are only intelligible from a contractualist
perspective.
I
conclude that death is, indeed, a harm to the one who dies, but solely because
death prevents future subjective satisfactions of desire (that is to say,
continued worthwhile existence), not because it prevents many of the persons
desires for the future from being objectively satisfied. Let me stress again,
however, that this thesis need not imply corresponding claims about the reasons
we have for fearing death, or about the reasons why killing is wrong. To claim
that the harm of death consists in preventing subjective satisfactions of
desire certainly does not imply that our only reason for fearing death is to
gain those satisfactions. On the contrary, almost any desire, whether it be a
desire for a feeling of satisfaction or an objective state of affairs, can give
one reason to fear death. Nor does that thesis imply that the only possible
direct objection to killing is that it prevents future subjective
satisfactions. On the contrary, contractualists, at least, will regard most
killings as wrong because they infringe autonomy, quite apart from the harm
that they do.
The
wrongness of killing
If the conclusions of the previous section
are correct, then it is clear that death is a harm to an animal in exactly the
same way that it is a harm to a human being - in both cases death (normally)
prevents future enjoyments and satisfactions that would otherwise have
occurred. It follows that if killing humans is directly wrong, for a utilitarian,
because of the harm that it causes - because it cuts off future worthwhile
existence - then on precisely the same grounds it must be directly wrong to
kill an animal. Since there can be no reason why an impartial observer should
refuse to recognize the enjoyments of an animal as having moral standing, it
would be mere speciesism to claim that it is wrong to prevent future enjoyments
in the case of a human being without saying the same for an animal.
This
is not yet to say that killing an animal would be as wrong as killing a human being, however. For as we shall see in
a later section, some have claimed that the distinctive enjoyments of human
beings have greater moral worth - are higher - than those of an animal. In
which case, although killing an animal would normally be directly wrong, there
might still be no question of weighing up animal lives against the life of a
human.
Even
the conclusion that killing an animal is directly wrong may depend very much on
what specific version of utilitarianism is endorsed, however. If utility is
cashed in terms of happiness or pleasure, then these are apparently states that
animals can enjoy just as much as we can. And then the fact that killing an
animal would prevent future pleasure will be a reason against it, just as it is
a reason against killing a human. But some utilitarians, including Singer,
think that utility is better cashed in terms of the fulfilment of preferences.[4]
On such an account, the main reason against killing a human being is that most
humans have a strong preference for going on living. But, it is claimed, most
(perhaps all) animals are incapable of having such a desire. An animal has
preferences for satisfaction as against suffering, but if animals are incapable
of conceptualising their own future non-existence, then they cannot have a
preference for their own future existence, as against non-existence. In Chapter
6 I shall consider to what extent these claims about the cognitive powers of
animals are true. For the moment, let us see what follows on the supposition
that they are.
A
preference-utilitarian approach
How should preference-utilitarianism be
understood? In particular, is it objective or subjective satisfactions of
preference that are to enter into calculations of utility? Clearly, I think,
the answer has to be that it is subjective satisfactions that matter, for at
least two reasons. First, notice that if it was objective satisfactions of
desire that were the basic utilitarian value, then in calculating utility we
should be obliged to give as much weight to the preferences of those long dead
as to those of the living. Suppose that all the inhabitants of Franksville in
the year 1900, for example, wanted very much that the statue of their beloved
founder Frank should stand in the town square for as long as the town lasted.
None of those people is now living, and the present inhabitants of Franksville
find the statue of Frank ugly, and wish to see it removed. Suppose that in the
interim the population of the town has shrunk. Then if it is objective
satisfactions that are to count, a preference-utilitarian might have to claim
that we are morally obliged to keep the statue where it is, since this is the
option that objectively satisfies the most desires. This seems intuitively
absurd.
The
second reason why preference-utilitarianism has to be understood in terms of
subjective rather than objective satisfactions is more deeply theoretical. It
is that it is impossible to see why an impartial benevolent observer should
give any weight to satisfactions of preference that are merely objective. For
why should such an observer count it as a good thing that people get what they
want, as such, independently of whether or not they believe that they have got
it? It is surely no part of benevolence to do something that satisfies
someones desire in circumstances in which the person will never know what has
happened.
To
make this point vivid, consider a variant of the example of Astrid, the
astronaut. As before, the statue of her late husband is destroyed soon after
her departure from Earth. I argued previously that this cannot be regarded as
harming her. Let us now ask whether, knowing her feeling on the matter, I would
act benevolently if I were to arrange for the statue to be rebuilt. It is
surely clear that I would not. Although such an action would objectively
satisfy Astrids desire, and although it might serve to express my sense of
mourning for her absence, it would not now be of any benefit to her. And
benevolence surely has to do with the provision of benefit and the prevention
of harm.
I
conclude that preference-utilitarianism has to be understood in terms of
subjective satisfactions of desire. We need to ask next, just which desires are to count. Suppose it
is replied first, that only presently existing desires are to be considered.
Then the desires of animals - for example, to avoid present suffering - may
make it wrong to hunt them or factory farm them. But since animals do not, it
is supposed, have desires for their own continued existence, it will not be
wrong to bring about their deaths. For the future desires of an animal, that
would be involved in its continued worthwhile existence if it were not killed,
are not to be counted at all, on the present proposal. Since human beings, in
contrast, do generally desire continued existence, we are obliged to respect
that desire, and killing will normally be directly wrong in consequence.
Notice
that the position we have reached here is in many ways a curious one. For so
long as an animal has active preferences - so long as it is hungry, or thirsty,
or is wanting to play - then the principle of equal consideration of interests
will require that we should, other things being equal, try to satisfy those
preferences. If there is nothing better that you can achieve with your time and
resources, then a preference-utilitarian will have to claim that you are
morally obliged to feed a hungry dog. But as soon as the animal no longer has
any active preferences - is sitting contentedly after eating, for example, or
has fallen asleep - then you would not be failing to fulfil any of its desires
if you killed it. So you are obliged to feed the dog while it is hungry, but as
soon as it is satisfied you may kill it. This combination of views seems
strange, to say the least.
More
importantly, if we are required to restrict attention to presently existing
preferences, then we can give no moral weight to preferences that we know will
exist in the future. For example, suppose that David is subject to temporary
fits of severe depression, during which nothing seems worthwhile. At the moment
he is suffering such a depression, and has no desire to go on living - he might
kill himself if he could only find the energy. But I know perfectly well that
by tomorrow he will be back to normal again. If it were only present desires
that counted, for a preference-utilitarian, then it would seem that there is no
direct moral objection to my killing David. But this is absurd. The fact that
he will again have a strong desire for continued life in the future is surely
sufficient to make such an action wrong.
Consider
another example to reinforce the point. Adolescents and young adults commonly
deny vigourously that they ever wish to have children. Indeed, there is no
reason to think that they are insincere. But we know that, for most of them,
the issue will strike them very differently in a few years time. Now other
things being equal, a policy of offering free sterilisations to such people
would surely be wrong, on the grounds that it prevents them from satisfying
their future desire to have children. But if only present desires were to be
counted, then there would be no direct moral objection to the policy.
I
conclude that a preference-utilitarian should certainly give weight to the
subjective satisfaction of both present and future desires. But then
utilitarians will again be in the position of having to say that there are
essentially the same reasons against killing animals as there are against
killing human beings. It may be true that animals do not presently have desires
for their own continued existence. But it is also normally true that they will
have desires for satisfactions and for avoidance of suffering in the future,
provided that they are not killed. And these desires should now be given equal
weight with any others. Since you should try to ensure the satisfaction of the
animals future desires, you are therefore normally obliged not to kill it.
A
human being will have, in general, many more desires at any given time than
will an animal. But this is not to the point. What matters, is the number (and
intensity) of the desires that can or will be satisfied. And here there need be
no difference between human and animal. So preserving the life of a human being
will not necessarily lead to more desire satisfaction than would preserving the
life of an animal. This will depend upon the details of the cases. The only
difference between killing animals and humans thus far, is that by not bringing
about the death of a human you will generally satisfy one more desire - namely,
the presently existing desire for continued life. But in the case of depressed
David there will not even be this difference.
If
a preference-utilitarian should give weight to both present and future desires,
then is the aim simply to maximise desire satisfaction (whether average or
total) overall? This can seem counter-intuitive. For one way to comply with it
would be to set about creating in people easily satisfied desires. Now, there
may not be anything especially wrong with creating such desires. I do not
particularly wish to commit myself to condemning consumer society at this
point. But there can surely be no moral obligation to support such a society,
merely on the grounds that with more and more desires continually being created
in people by advertising, more and more desires are continually being
satisfied.
There
are difficult issues arising here for preference-utilitarianism. Some have
attempted to overcome them by retreating to the notion of a rational desire, claiming that only
present and future desires that qualify as rational ones are to be given moral
weight. (Another issue arising, is whether it is only the future desires of
actually existing creatures that are to be counted. This comes up especially in
connection with population policy.[5])
The notion of a rational desire is notoriously difficult to define. For our
purposes it will be enough to distinguish two broad approaches to the problem.
On the one hand, we could explain the notion of a rational desire in terms of
the modes of desire-formation that are normal for the cognition of the creature
involved. This would allow animals, and non-rational agents generally, to have
rational desires. But then on the other hand, we could explain the notion of a
rational desire in terms of the sorts of processes of thinking and reasoning
that are distinctive of rational agents. Taking this option would exclude the
future desires of animals from the moral domain once more.
To
take this second option would be blatantly speciesist, however. It is
impossible to see any reason why an impartial benevolent observer should
discount a particular desire, merely because the creature in question had not
subjected it to intellectual scrutiny. It is easy to see why such an observer
might discount the present desires of depressed David, or desires produced by
advertising, hypnosis, or drug addiction. For these desires have been created
and sustained by processes that are disruptive of the normal cognitive lives of
the agents involved. But there can be no reason why such an observer, if
genuinely impartial, should discount or give less weight to the desires of an
animal, merely because that animal had failed to engage in such activities as
thinking carefully about alternatives, and checking through the presuppositions
of its desire for false beliefs.
I
conclude that utilitarians, of whatever variety, are committed to saying that
the killing of an animal is almost always directly wrong, just as is the
killing of a human. The question now, is whether a utilitarian must say that
killing an animal is just as wrong,
provided that the number and intensity of the desires or pleasures involved are
roughly proportional.
The
value of life
In addition to the appeal to
preference-utilitarianism criticised above, Singer has quite another argument
for saying that killing a rational agent - a person - is worse than killing an
animal. It is that the lives of rational agents are intrinsically more valuable
than the lives of at least most kinds of animal.[6]
Now this is not - and had better not be - an appeal to any form of moral
intuitionism, which we considered and rejected in the opening chapter. The idea
is not that the greater value of human lives is an objective fact, apprehended
by us through a special faculty of moral intuition. Rather, Singers idea is to
deploy a version of the classical utilitarian distinction between higher and
lower pleasures, transformed now into a distinction between higher and lower
modes of life.
(It
is worth noting that Regan, too, feels obliged to deploy a variant of this
distinction, although he is by no means a utilitarian. For he wishes to explain
our intuition that, in a case where four men and a dog are adrift on a
life-raft that can only safely support four creatures, it is right that the dog
should be the one to be thrown off.[7]
Regan thinks that the basis for our intuition is that the distinctive
enjoyments of a dog have less intrinsic value than those of human beings. Since
Regan is not a utilitarian, this is presumably supposed to be one of those
objective facts about the world that we are somehow - and mysteriously - to
apprehend through the procedure of reflective equilibrium.)
The
criterion for a pleasure, or a mode of living, being higher, for a utilitarian,
is that anyone who has had experience of both would prefer it. Now, we have all
had experience of animal pleasures - of a full stomach and a doze in the sun,
for example. Yet no one would seriously wish for a life that contained only
such pleasures, without the distinctively intellectual enjoyments of reading a
novel, listening to music, or engaging in animated conversation with a friend.
So it appears to follow that a mode of life that is distinctively human is more
valuable than the life of an animal. As Mill famously maintained, it is better
to be Socrates dissatisfied than a pig satisfied.
It
is easy to see the rationale, for utilitarians, of the distinction between
higher and lower pleasures in simple cases. For it provides them with a way of
ranking pleasures, in terms other than intensity and duration, that all should
rationally agree to. For example, suppose that everyone who has had experience
of both, prefers the taste of pineapple to the taste of dry bread. This gives
us reason to think that the same would hold even of those who have never tasted
pineapple, were they to do so. Suppose Poppy is such a person. Then knowing
these facts, she ought rationally to agree that, other things being equal, it
is more important that someone should have the pleasure of eating a pineapple
than that she herself should have the pleasure of eating dry bread. For she
should acknowledge that she too, were she to experience it, would rank the
former pleasure higher.
Problems
begin to arise, however, in cases where the character of the subject must
undergo substantial change in order to appreciate the new range of pleasures.
For this may involve a corresponding inability to appreciate previous
enjoyments. For example, many years of disciplined study may be required to
appreciate certain intellectual pleasures, such as the pursuit of philosophy or
of higher mathematics. But then it may be that the changes of character
necessary to appreciate these pleasures unfit one for full enjoyment of
singing, dancing, and spontaneity. In which case, the person who has had
experience of both sorts of pleasure (that is, the intellectual) is no longer a
competent judge of their relative values.
These
problems become even more acute when we are trying to compare modes of life
across different species. How are we, fairly and realistically, to compare the
life of a horse with the life of a human being, given the vast changes in
cognitive powers and dispositions that would be necessary to move from the one
to the other? Singer attempts to circumvent this problem through the use of an
imaginary device.[8] He asks us
to imagine a creature with the power to transform itself into each mode of life
in turn - living first as a horse, then as a human, and then in some mode
different from either, but retaining an exact memory of what each of the first
two ways of living was like. Is it not plausible, he asks, that such a creature
would judge the life of the human to be more valuable than the life of the
horse?
Singer
has clearly biased the issue here, however. For note that the creature in
question is supposed to have articulate memories of its previous existences,
and is supposed to be able to entertain sophisticated judgements about the
relative values of those existences. In these respects the mode of existence of
that creature is much closer to ours than to that of the horse. Small wonder,
then, that such a creature should prefer the life of a human, since it might be
expected to judge the life of the horse to be dull and unvaried by comparison.
Yet these are, of course, distinctively human
values, reflecting our relative cognitive complexity and sophistication.
What
we have to do is, in fact, well nigh impossible. We have to imagine an
impartial benevolent observer - a Martian, perhaps - with interests and mode of
cognition no more similar to ours than to those of the horse, who nevertheless
has full inside knowledge of what our respective modes of existence are like.
In so far as I am able to form any conception of such an observer, I can see no
reason why they should judge our human existence to be more valuable than that
of the horse. I conclude that while the distinction between higher and lower
pleasures may be intelligible and useful for a utilitarian in connection with
simple cases, where it is merely lack of experience that prevents a direct
comparison, that distinction is useless in attempting to rank pleasures and
modes of life across species, with their differing modes of cognition.
The
electrode workers
I have been arguing that there is no
principled way in which utilitarians can show a human life to be more valuable
than the life of an animal. It has to be admitted, however, that there is a
powerful intuitive appeal behind the sorts of common-sense beliefs that
utilitarians try to capture by means of the distinction between higher and
lower pleasures. What I shall maintain in this section, is that this appeal is
only really explicable from the stand-point of contractualism - thus driving
one more nail into the coffin of the utilitarian approach to the animals issue.
Consider
the following imaginary example, which is grounded in the well known fact that
the brains of many mammals, including rats and monkeys, contain a so-called
pleasure centre. If an electrode is inserted into this centre, then the
animal in question will engage in an arbitrary activity - such as pressing a
bar - for hours on end, in order to have its pleasure centre stimulated. Now
imagine that such a centre were discovered in human beings. Suppose also, that
some enterprising employers begin to offer implants to their manual workers, in
such a way that those workers will have their pleasure centres stimulated every
time they make one of the movements required for their work - say pulling a
lever. Those who accept the offer soon come to live for their work, and the
attendant pleasure it provides. They gladly work a sixteen hour day, eat on the
job, and return home at night only to sleep. They say they cannot understand,
now, how anyone else can choose to live differently. Yet there is, surely, a
powerful common-sense intuition that their mode of life is impoverished, and
that it might be morally wrong to opt for an implant-life, say by bringing
ones child into the factory to be wired up.
It
is easy to understand how we, now, would have very good reason not to opt for
an implant-life. For all of our current desires, interests, and projects would
be lost sight of in such a life. We therefore have almost as much reason to
fear an implant as we have to fear death - everything we presently care about
would be lost. But at the same time we must recognize that someone who is
already an electrode worker has just as much reason to fear the removal of
their electrode. For in their case, too, the result would be the loss of
everything that they presently care about, in exchange for a set of interests
and concerns that they do not currently share. So there is nothing in this that
can justify the claim that the one mode of life has, in itself, a greater moral
value than the other. (Of course there are all sorts of secondary ways in which
those who are not electrode workers may be more useful to other people.) Nor
can a utilitarian provide a justification for such a claim through the
distinction between higher and lower pleasures. For the positions of each of
the two groups with respect to the other will be symmetrical - I presume that
each would prefer their present mode of existence to their past one.
Yet
the intuition that there is a moral difference here is surely very powerful.
Suppose, for example, that the implant has to be made, and wired up regularly,
quite early in life in order to be fully successful. You are now considering
whether to have an implant made in the brain of your ten year old son, Imri. If
you do so, you know that you will be more or less ensuring his future
happiness! For he will then have just one overwhelming desire, that will be
easily, and almost continually, satisfied. Yet it would be very wrong of you,
surely, to commit Imri to such a future. For in the circumstances you know
that, once wired up, he will never want to change - indeed, he will never again
have a serious desire for anything else.
This
intuition is only really explicable from a contractualist perspective, given
that we believe that the electrode workers fail to retain the capacity for
planning and choosing that is distinctive of rational agency. (For extended
discussion of what is involved in the notion of a rational agent, see Chapter
6.) I think we are inclined to maintain that the desire for pleasure so dominates
their cognition as to leave no place for the exercise of genuine autonomy. In
fact, their situation is exactly like that of a willing drug addict, only
without the debilitating effects of drug addiction. The electrode workers
retain the potential for rational
agency, of course, since if unplugged they would soon return to normal. Indeed,
there is a real sense in which they continue to have the capacity for it too, since their minds presumably retain the
cognitive structures necessary for autonomous action. It is merely that their
implant prevents them from exercising this capacity - just as cotton wool
packaging can prevent a brittle glass from exercising its capacity to be
broken. (Seen in this light, there would then be a powerful case for rescuing
the electrode workers from their plight, overriding their own vigourous
resistance - though this is not the point I particularly wish to focus on.)
What
this then means is that it will be us,
rather than the electrode workers, who get to frame the terms of the moral
contract. For moral rules, within contractualism, are created by rational,
choosing, autonomous agents. To put the point slightly differently, the
electrode workers cannot reasonably reject any proposed system of rules, since
their situation is such that they are no longer capable of exercising their
capacity for rational decision. So they can be allowed to have no objection to
any rules that might be proposed, including those that would prevent Imri from
becoming an implant boy. What would be more natural, then, than that we should
decide to outlaw practices that undermine the exercise of genuine autonomy, as
would becoming an electrode worker in childhood? For our status as autonomous
agents is presupposed in almost everything that we care about. What therefore
emerges, is that a contractualist should claim, in a way that a utilitarian
cannot, that it would be directly wrong to take Imri into the factory to be
wired up - which is just what our common-sense intuition tells us.
Life
as a journey
Singer has, more recently, made yet another
attempt to ground his view that the lives of rational agents are more valuable
than the lives of animals, while retaining his utilitarian perspective. He
argues that a human life may usefully be conceived of as a journey.[9]
If I am travelling on a journey, but am forced to abandon it, my disappointment
will generally be in proportion to my nearness to the goal, and to the amount
of effort that has gone in to the travelling, which now turns out to have been
wasted. So, too, in life, Singer thinks. Much of early life is mere preparation
for what follows, and many of us have long-term projects that give shape to,
and help to make sense of, our lives. It is then less tragic if death should
occur early in childhood, when the journey has barely begun, or late in life,
when most goals have been attained, and most projects completed. There is also
held to be less direct moral objection to killing human beings at these stages
in their lives.
Most
importantly for our purposes, Singer argues that the point at which the journey
of life begins, from the perspective of those who travel, is the point at which
they first begin to conceive of themselves as having a future and a past, and
to think of some of their current activities as preparatory for the future. For
suppose that this were so, and that most animals lack such a conception of
themselves altogether (an assumption we shall examine in Chapter 6). Then such
an animal will never have embarked on the journey, and death, for them, will be
no tragedy, since it does not interrupt any journey. Nor will there be any
direct moral objection to killing such a creature.
I
can see no theoretical rationale for these views, however. Why should an
impartial benevolent observer give less weight to (or discount altogether) the
interests of someone who is standing still, as against someone who has embarked
on a journey? Those who stay at home have desires, purposes, and feelings no
less than those who go abroad. What may be true, is that an observer who is
comparing two travellers will count as more serious an interruption in the
journey of the one who is closest to completion, other things being equal. For,
having invested more, that person will have more to lose. But this provides no
ground for thinking that an impartial observer will only consider the interests
of those who travel (that is, of those who have long term plans and projects).
In which case, we have been given no reason why a utilitarian should maintain
that the death of an animal, or a baby, is less serious than the death of a
rational agent. On the contrary, the fact that death prevents future
satisfaction of desires in all these cases provides the same (and the only)
direct utilitarian rationale against killing.
It
is true that the judgements that Singer seeks to explain through the metaphor
of a journey have an intuitive appeal, for many people. Many do feel that the
death of a baby, or an old person, is less of a tragedy, from the perspective
of the one who dies, than the death of someone in the prime of life. But I
think these intuitions are not utilitarian ones, and certainly provide no basis
on which a utilitarian can claim that the death of an animal is less morally
significant than the death of a rational agent. Let me explain.
Take
the case of babies first. Anyone who has contractualist sympathies might be
expected to share the thought that the death of a baby, by accident or from
natural causes, is less of a tragedy, from the perspective of the baby, than
the death of a normal adult. For such people may be expected to value rational
agency above all else, and the baby is presumably not, as yet, a rational
agent. (It is arguable, indeed, that all rational agents will value the
possession of rational agency highly, quite apart from whatever moral views
they may hold.[10]) But it
should be emphasised that this is not to claim that a contractualist will count
the killing of a baby to be less
serious than the killing of an adult, as we shall see in the next chapter. Nor
is there any way in which utilitarians can motivate the claim that the death of
a baby is less morally serious, unless they retreat to a form of indefensible
intuitionism, claiming that it is an objective fact about the world that those
who have a conception of their past and future are more valuable than those who
do not. For, as we have seen, there is no reason why an impartial observer
should discount the present and future desires of the baby, merely because they
are not yet linked together by any overall life-plan.
Now
consider the case of the very old. Again, many share the feeling that the death
of such a person is less of a tragedy than the death of a young adult. But
these judgements serve mainly to express a comparison with reasonable
expectations, made to console the living (like saying He had a good innings)
- which need not be a point of view shared by the one who has died. It is true
that some old people may gradually wind down their activities and projects as
they near the term of their expected span. And in some such cases it may
rightly be said that the person had little more to live for by the time of
their death. But others keep going as they have always done, as if death were
only for others. (Interestingly, members of the latter group tend also to live
longer.) There is nothing here to support the view that life, as such, may be
thought of as a journey - only that some people may conceive of their lives in
some such terms.
Reflective
disequilibrium
I conclude that utilitarians are committed to
the view that there is the same sort of direct moral objection to killing
animals as there is to killing humans. For there are essentially the same
utilitarian reasons against such killings in both cases - that killing would
prevent future enjoyment, and that not killing is necessary if the organism is
to have its future preferences fulfilled. Moreover, there is no coherent way
for a utilitarian to claim that the life of a human being has, in itself,
greater moral value than the life of an animal, without degenerating into moral
intuitionism. The only valid utilitarian reasons remaining, for why it will
generally be worse to kill a human being than to kill an animal, are extrinsic
ones. These are first, that human beings tend to live longer than most animals,
so a greater extent of life will generally be cut off by death. And second,
that the death of a human being will generally cause much suffering to friends
and relatives, in a way that the death of an animal will rarely cause suffering
to other animals.
Can
such a position be acceptable under reflective equilibrium? I believe not.
Consider the following development of the example of Kenneth, the kennel owner,
first presented in Chapter 1. You arrive at a fire in his dogs home to find
Kenneth unconscious on the floor, while the dogs are still locked in their
cages. You judge that you have just enough time, either to drag Kenneth to
safety, or to unlock the cages, but not both. Suppose you also know that
Kenneth is quite old, and is something of a recluse who lives entirely for his
work, without anyone to care for him. In these circumstances a utilitarian is
clearly committed to the view that you should opt to rescue the dogs. For this
is obviously the way to ensure the greatest future pleasure, and/or the
greatest future desire satisfaction. Utilitarians cannot avoid this conclusion
by discounting the interests of the dogs altogether, without engaging in a form
of speciesism which must be unacceptable from their own perspective.
This
conclusion is morally outrageous, however, as are its further consequences.
Once it is accepted that the killing of an animal is just as morally serious,
in general, as the killing of a human being, then those practices that involve
the regular slaughter of animals, such as farming and some forms of animal
experimentation, will seem to fall within the same moral category as the Nazi
holocaust. And then any form of opposition to such practices, of whatever
degree of violence, will seem eminently justified. In fact, those animals rights
activists who pursue the methods of terrorism - planting bombs and poisoning
baby-foods - are only following utilitarianism through to its logical, but
morally abhorrent, conclusion.
Our
common-sense, pre-theoretical, view is that it would be very wrong to place the
lives of many dogs over the life of a single (albeit old and friendless) human.
This belief is probably too firmly held, in the case of most of us, to be
shaken by theoretical argument. (Recall from Chapter 1, indeed, that it is a
belief shared even by those philosophers who have been most vociferous in
defence of animals, namely Regan and Singer.) Moreover, since this common-sense
belief will prove to be retained under contractualism (as we shall see in later
chapters) but is lost under utilitarianism, and since contractualism is in
other respects just as, if not more, theoretically satisfying than
utilitarianism, the correct response is to reject utilitarianism altogether. At
any rate, the utilitarian approach to animal lives seems just as unacceptable
as we found the utilitarian approach to animal suffering to be in the last
chapter.
Summary
Death is a harm to the one who dies only in so far as it prevents future worthwhile existence. Yet our reason for fearing death is that continued life will be presupposed by almost all of our desires. From a utilitarian perspective there is essentially the same direct moral objection to killing an animal as there is to killing a human - namely, that the death prevents future enjoyments, and that not being killed is a necessary condition for the future desires of the creature to be satisfied. From the same perspective there is no reason to count the life of an animal as less valuable than the life of a rational agent. I have argued that these consequences are too extreme to be believed.
[1] For further discussion of the issue, see my Introducing Persons, chs. 3 & 7.
[2] See particularly Thomas Nagel, Death', in his Mortal Questions.
[3] Similar points are made by Joel Feinberg, Harm and Self-Interest' in P. Hacker & J. Raz eds., Law, Morality and Society (Oxford University Press, 1977).
[4] See Practical Ethics, ch. 4.
[5] For discussion of the many puzzles involved, see Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford University Press, 1984), part IV.
[6] See Practical Ethics, pp. 88-90.
[7] See Animal Rights, p. 324.
[8] See Practical Ethics, p. 89.
[9] See Life's Uncertain Voyage' in P. Pettit, R. Sylvan & J. Norman eds., Metaphysics and Morality (Blackwell, 1987).
[10] On this, see my Introducing Persons, ch. 8.